Cardinality with Applications to Computability - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Cardinality with Applications to Computability

Description:

Incorrect Proof Incorrect Proof: Group the strings by their first letter {a, aa, ab, }, {b, ba, bb, }, {c, ca, cb, }. Within those groups, ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:33
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 40
Provided by: RobbKo5
Learn more at: https://people.hsc.edu
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Cardinality with Applications to Computability


1
Cardinality with Applications to Computability
  • Lecture 33
  • Section 7.5
  • Wed, Apr 12, 2006

2
Cardinality of Finite Sets
  • For finite sets, the cardinality of a set is the
    number of elements in the set.
  • For a finite set A, let A denote the
    cardinality of A.

3
Cardinality of Infinite Sets
  • We wish to extend the notion of cardinality to
    infinite sets.
  • Rather than talk about the number of elements
    in an infinite set, for infinite sets A and B, we
    will speak of the cardinality of A.
  • A having the same cardinality as B, or
  • A having a lesser cardinality than B, or
  • A having a greater cardinality than B.

4
Definition of Same Cardinality
  • Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if
    there exists a one-to-one correspondence from A
    to B.
  • Write A B.
  • Note that this definition works for finite sets,
    too.

5
Definition of Same Cardinality
  • Theorem If A B and B C, then A
    C.

6
Same Cardinality
  • Theorem 2Z Z, where 2Z represents the
    even integers.
  • Proof
  • Define f Z ? 2Z by f(n) 2n.
  • Clearly, f is a one-to-one correspondence.
  • Therefore, 2Z Z.

7
Cardinality of Z
  • Theorem Z Z, where Z represents the
    positive integers.
  • Proof
  • Define f Z ? Z by
  • f(n) 2n if n gt 0
  • f(n) 1 2n if n ? 0.
  • Verify that f is a one-to-one correspondence.
  • Therefore, Z Z.

8
Definition of Lesser Cardinality
  • Set A has a cardinality less than or equal to the
    cardinality of a set B if there exists a
    one-to-one function from A to B.
  • Write A ? B.
  • Then A lt B means that there is a one-to-one
    function from A to B, but there is not a
    one-to-one correspondence from A to B.

9
Order Relations Among Infinite Sets
  • Corollary If A ? B and B ? C, then
    A ? C.
  • Corollary If A ? B, then A ? B.
  • Proof
  • Let A ? B.
  • Define the function f A ?? B by f(a) a.
  • Clearly, f is one-to-one.
  • Therefore, A ? B.

10
Definition of Greater Cardinality
  • We may define A ? B to mean B ? A and
    define A gt B to mean B lt A.

11
Definition of Greater Cardinality
  • Theorem A ? B if and only if there exists an
    onto function from A to B.

B
A
12
Definition of Greater Cardinality
  • Theorem A ? B if and only if there exists an
    onto function from A to B.

f
one-to-one function
B
A
13
Definition of Greater Cardinality
  • Theorem A ? B if and only if there exists an
    onto function from A to B.

g
its inverse
B
A
14
Definition of Greater Cardinality
  • Theorem A ? B if and only if there exists an
    onto function from A to B.

g
onto function
B
A
15
Order Relations Among Infinite Sets
  • Corollary If A ? B and B ? C, then
    A ? C.
  • Corollary If A ? B and B ? A, then
    A B.
  • Etc.

16
Cardinality of the Interval (0, 1)
  • Theorem The interval (0, 1) has the same
    cardinality as R.
  • Proof
  • The function f(x) (x ½)? establishes that
  • (0, 1) (?/2, ?/2).
  • The function g(x) tan x establishes that
  • (?/2, ?/2) R.
  • Therefore, (0, 1) R.

17
Countable Sets
  • A set is countable if it either is finite or has
    the same cardinality as Z.
  • Examples 2Z and Z are countable.
  • To show that an infinite set is countable, it
    suffices to give an algorithm for listing, or
    enumerating, the elements in such a way that each
    element appears exactly once in the list.

18
Example Countable Sets
  • Theorem The number of strings of finite length
    consisting of the characters a, b, and c is
    countable.
  • Correct proof
  • Group the strings by length ?, a, b, c,
  • aa, ab, , cc,
  • Arrange the strings alphabetically within groups.

19
Canonical Ordering
  • This gives the canonical order
  • ?, a, b, c, aa, ab, ac, ba, , cc,
  • aaa, aab, , ccc, aaaa, aaab, ,
  • where ? denotes the empty string.
  • Consider the string bbabc.
  • How do we know that it will appear in the list?
  • In what position will it appear?

20
Incorrect Proof
  • Incorrect Proof
  • Group the strings by their first letter a, aa,
    ab, , b, ba, bb, , c, ca, cb, .
  • Within those groups, group those words by their
    second letter, and so on.
  • List the a-group first, the b-group second, and
    the c-group last.
  • In what position will we find the string bbabc?
    the string abc? the string aaaab?

21
Example Countable Sets
  • Theorem Q is countable.
  • Proof
  • Arrange the positive rationals in an infinite
    two-dimensional array.

1/1 1/2 1/3 1/4
2/1 2/2 2/3 2/4
3/1 3/2 3/3 3/4
4/1 4/2 4/3 4/4

22
Proof of Countability of Q
  • Then list the numbers by diagonals

1/1 1/2 1/3 1/4
2/1 2/2 2/3 2/4
3/1 3/2 3/3 3/4
4/1 4/2 4/3 4/4

23
Proof of Countability of Q
  • We get the list
  • 1/1, 2/1, 1/2, 3/1, 2/2, 1/3, 4/1, 2/3, 3/2,
  • 1/4, 5/1, 4/2, 3/3, 2/4, 1/5,
  • Then remove the repeated fractions, i.e., the
    unreduced ones
  • 1/1, 2/1, 1/2, 3/1, 1/3, 4/1, 2/3, 3/2, 1/4,
  • 5/1, 1/5,
  • In what position will we find 3/5?

24
False Proof of the Countability of Q
  • Incorrect listing 1
  • List the rationals from in order according to
    size.
  • Incorrect listing 2
  • List all fractions with denominator 1 first.
  • Follow that list with all fractions with
    denominator 2.
  • And so on.

25
Uncountable Sets
  • A set is uncountable if it is not countable.

26
R is Uncountable
  • Theorem R is uncountable.
  • Proof
  • It suffices to show that the interval (0, 1) is
    uncountable.
  • Suppose (0, 1) is countable.
  • Then we may list its members 1st, 2nd, 3rd, and
    so on.

27
R is Uncountable
  • Label them x1, x2, x3, and so on.
  • Represent each xi by its decimal expansion.
  • x1 0.d11d12d13
  • x2 0.d21d22d23
  • x3 0.d31d32d33
  • and so on, where dij is the j-th decimal digit
    of xi.

28
R is Uncountable
  • Form a number x 0.d1d2d3 as follows.
  • Define di 0 if dii ? 0.
  • Define di 1 if dii 0.
  • Then x ? (0, 1), but x is not in the list x1, x2,
    x3,
  • This is a contradiction.
  • Therefore, R is not countable.

29
Functions from Z to Z
  • Theorem The number of functions
  • f Z ? Z is uncountable.
  • Proof
  • Suppose there are only countably many.
  • List them f1, f2, f3,

30
Functions from Z to Z
  • Define a function f Z ? Z as follows.
  • f(i) 0 if fi(i) ? 0.
  • f(i) 1 if fi(i) 0.
  • Then f(i) ? fi(i) for all i in Z.
  • Therefore, f is not in the list.
  • This is a contradiction.
  • Therefore, the set is uncountable.

31
Number of Computer Programs
  • Theorem The set of all computer programs is
    countable.
  • Proof
  • Once compiled, a computer program is a finite
    string of 0s and 1s.
  • The set of all computer programs is a subset of
    the set of all finite binary strings.

32
Number of Computer Programs
  • This set may be listed
  • ?,
  • 0, 1,
  • 00, 01, 10, 11,
  • 000, 001, 010, , 111,
  • 0000, 0001, 0010, 0011, , 1111,
  • Therefore, it is countable.
  • As a subset of this set, the set of computer
    programs is countable.

33
Computability of Functions
  • Corollary There exists a function f Z ? Z
    which cannot be computed by any computer program.

34
Subsets of N
  • There are uncountably many subsets of N.
  • However, there are countably many finite subsets
    of N.
  • Can you prove it?

35
Cardinality of the Power Set
  • Theorem For any set A,
  • A lt ?(A).
  • Proof
  • There is a one-to-one function f A ? ?(A)
    defined by f(x) x.
  • Therefore, A ? ?(A).
  • We must prove that there does not exist a
    one-to-one correspondence from A to ?(A).

36
Proof, continued
  • That is, we must prove that there does not exist
    an onto function from A to ?(A).
  • Suppose g A ? ?(A) is onto.
  • For every x ? A, either x ? g(x) or x ? g(x).
  • Define a set B x ? A x ? g(x).
  • Then B ? ?(A), since B ? A.
  • So B g(a) for some a ? A (since g is onto, by
    assumption).

37
Proof, continued
  • Is a ? g(a)?
  • Case 1 Suppose a ? g(a).
  • Then a ? B, by the definition of B.
  • But B g(a), so a ? g(a), a contradiction.
  • Case 2 Suppose a ? g(a).
  • Then a ? B, by the definition of B.
  • But B g(a), so a ? g(a), a contradiction.

38
Proof, concluded
  • Either way, we have a contradiction.
  • Therefore, no such one-to-one function exists.
  • Thus, A lt ?(A).

39
Hierarchy of Cardinalities
  • Beginning with Z, consider the sets
  • Z, ?(Z), ?(?(Z)),
  • Each set has a cardinality strictly greater than
    its predecessor.
  • Z lt ?(Z) lt ?(?(Z)) lt
  • These cardinalities are denoted ?0,?1,?2,
    (aleph-naught, aleph-one, aleph-two, )
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com