Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld 18791918 was an American jurist' He was the author of the seminal Fundamental - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 18
About This Presentation
Title:

Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld 18791918 was an American jurist' He was the author of the seminal Fundamental

Description:

He was the author of the seminal Fundamental Legal Conceptions, As Applied in ... noticed that even respected jurists conflate various meanings of the term right, ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:359
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 19
Provided by: Offi196
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld 18791918 was an American jurist' He was the author of the seminal Fundamental


1
??????????
  • ??? ??

2
??
  • Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld (1879-1918) was an
    American jurist. He was the author of the seminal
    Fundamental Legal Conceptions, As Applied in
    Judicial Reasoning and Other Legal Essays,
    published in 1919.
  • During his life, he published only a handful of
    law journal articles. At his death, the material
    forming the basis of Fundamental Legal
    Conceptions was derived from two articles in the
    Yale Law Journal (1913) and (1917) that had been
    partially revised with a view to publication.

3
?????
  • Editorial work was undertaken to complete the
    revisions and the book was published with the
    inclusion of the manuscript notes that Hohfeld
    had left, plus seven other essays.
  • The work remains a powerful contribution to
    modern understanding of the nature of rights and
    the implications of liberty. To reflect this
    continuing importance, a chair at Yale University
    is named after him, which is currently held by
    Jules Coleman.

4
?????????
  • Hohfeld noticed that even respected jurists
    conflate various meanings of the term right,
    sometimes switching senses of the word several
    times in a single sentence. He wrote that such
    imprecision of language indicated a concomitant
    imprecision of thought, and thus also of the
    resulting legal conclusions. In order to both
    facilitate reasoning and clarify rulings, he
    attempted to disambiguate the term rights by
    breaking it into eight distinct concepts. To
    eliminate ambiguity, he defined these terms
    relative to one another, grouping them into four
    pairs of Jural Opposites and four pairs of Jural
    Correlatives.

5
????
  • Jural Opposites
  • 1. Right/No-Right 2. Privilege/Duty
  • 3. Power/Disability 4. Immunity/Liability
  • Jural Corelatives
  • 1. Right/Duty 2. Privilege/No-Right
  • 3. Power/Liability 4. Immunity/Disability

6
???????
7
??????
  • Some philosophers and political scientists make a
    distinction between claim rights and liberty
    rights. A claim right is a right which entails
    responsibilities, duties, or obligations on other
    parties regarding the right-holder. In contrast,
    a liberty right is a right which does not entail
    obligations on other parties, but rather only
    freedom or permission for the right-holder.

8
?????
  • The other two terms of Hohfeld's analysis, powers
    and immunities, refer to second-order liberties
    and claims, respectively. Powers are liberty
    rights regarding the modification of first-order
    rights, e.g. the U.S. Congress has certain
    positive powers to modify some of U.S. citizens'
    legal rights, inasmuch as it can impose or remove
    legal duties. Immunities, conversely, are claim
    rights regarding the modification of first-order
    rights, e.g. U.S. citizens have, per their
    Constitution, certain negative immunities
    limiting the positive powers of the U.S. Congress
    to modify their legal rights. As such, immunities
    and powers are often subsumed within claims and
    liberties by later authors.

9
????????
  • ?????
  • ??
  • ????(???)
  • ???
  • ?????(?????????)
  • ??????????????
  • ?????????
  • ?????
  • ????????

10
??
  • Hohfeld argued that right and duty are corelative
    concepts, i.e. the one must always be matched by
    the other. If A has a right against B, this is
    equivalent to B having a duty to honour A's
    right. If B has no duty, that means that B has
    liberty, i.e. B can do whatever he or she pleases
    because B has no duty to refrain from doing it,
    and A has no right to prohibit B from doing so.
    Each individual is located within a matrix of
    relationships with other individuals.

11
????????
  • By summing the rights held and duties owed across
    all these relationships, the analyst can identify
    both the degree of liberty an individual would
    be considered to have perfect liberty if it is
    shown that no-one has a right to prevent the
    given act and whether the concept of liberty is
    comprised by commonly followed practices, thereby
    establishing general moral principles and civil
    rights.

12
??????????
  • Hohfeld defines the corelatives in terms of the
    relationships between two individuals. In the
    theory of "in rem rights", there is a direct
    relationship between a person and a thing. Real
    rights are in this respect unlike claim rights or
    "rights in personam", which by nature must be
    exercised against a person the best example
    being when someone is owed money by another.

13
???????
  • Hohfeld demonstrates that this way of
    understanding rights in general is wrong. In
    particular, Hohfeld demonstrates that there is no
    such thing as a legal relation between a person
    and a thing, since a legal relation always
    operates between two people. As the legal
    relations between any two people are complex, it
    is helpful to break them down into their simplest
    forms.

14
????????????
  • Hohfeld replaces the concept of right in
    personam by paucital right and "right in rem"
    by a compound or aggregate of "multital rights".
    Rights held by a person against one or a few
    definite persons are paucital (or in personam),
    and rights held by a person against a large
    indefinite class of people are multital (or in
    rem). A contract right is paucital (or "in
    personam") because it can only be enforced
    against the specific parties to the contract. A
    property right is multital (or "in rem") because
    a landowner has the right to exclude not only
    specific people from his land but the whole
    world.

15
??????????
  • The landowner has many rights, privileges,
    powers, and immunities his multital rights are
    composed of many paucital rights. For example,
    the owner has a right that others do not step on
    his land but there is not just one such right
    against a mass of persons (the community), but
    many separate although usually identical paucital
    rights with this content (as many instances as
    there are people in the community). This is what
    Hohfeld calls "multital rights.

16
?????
  • Consider also the definition of liberty. In
    Hohfeldian analysis, liberty is defined by an
    absence both of a duty and of a right. B is free
    because he has no obligation to recognise any of
    A's rights. That does not deny that B might
    decide to do what A wants because that is the
    essence of liberty. Nor does it deny the
    possibility that B might accept a duty to A to
    give a benefit to C. In that situation, C would
    have no right and would have to rely on A to
    enforce the duty.

17
????????
  • The truth is that liberty is significant from
    both a legal and a moral point of view because
    only liberty ensures that an individual has
    control over his or her choices on whether and
    how to act. If something interferes with this
    choice, the natural reaction is to resent it and
    to seek a remedy.

18
?????
  • The corelative between right and duty inevitably
    describes the way in which two people are limited
    in their choices to act, and the outside observer
    cannot capture the legal and moral implications
    without examining the nature of the right held by
    A. Hence, this relationship is qualitatively
    different. An interference with liberty would be
    considered wrongful without having to ask for
    detailed evidence. Yet whether A's relationship
    with B is morally suspect could only be
    determined by evaluating evidence on precisely
    what B's duty requires B to do or not to do.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com