Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 81
About This Presentation
Title:

Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1

Description:

How induction can be used to justify our claims (as individuals) to be reliable observers. ... This undermines logical atomism, the idea that basic concepts are all ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:231
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 82
Provided by: bryson3
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1


1
Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1
  • Dispensing with the given sense data first.

2
The project
  • Sellars aim here is to sort out his philosophy
    of mind while retaining an empiricist
    epistemology.
  • Issues
  • The given Sellars rejects the notion that
    anything is immediately apprehended in propria
    persona there is no transparent awareness of
    anything.
  • Sense-data talk and the relation between our use
    of seems and ordinary observation reports.
  • How induction can be used to justify our claims
    (as individuals) to be reliable observers.
  • Relations between rationalism and empiricism in
    our philosophical tradition. Sellars wants to
    reconcile these, recognizing the importance of
    empirical evidence while also recognizing the
    crucial role concepts play in all knowledge.

3
The Given
  • So what is the given?
  • Not just something that we observe directly, i.e.
    a claim we accept without inferring it from other
    claims weve accepted.
  • Many things have been said to be given sense
    contents, material objects, universals,
    propositions, real connections, first principles,
    even givenness itself.
  • A framework that is part of many different
    philosophical positions.
  • Among the first forms to be criticized were
    intuited first principles, synthetic necessary
    connections.
  • Sellars aims to root it out entirely, not just
    some particular forms of it.

4
Why attack the given?
  • Cognitive psychology our accounts of what and
    how we know need to fit with our natural
    understanding of what humans can learn to detect
    and discriminate.
  • The neo-Hobbesian picture of humans that ends
    Phenomenalism is incompatible with a view of
    knowledge involving an immediate link between a
    logically simple subject and some fact about the
    world.
  • All knowledge is expressed in language, and
    language can shift and change in many ways.
  • Our relation to the community and the conceptual
    capacities that arise through language
    instruction are indispensable elements in any
    knowledge we have, no matter how direct (i.e.
    non-inferential) it is.

5
First target Sense data
  • For x to be sensed is for it to be the object of
    an act.
  • A sense content is a possible object for such an
    act.
  • Kinds of sensing may just reduce to the kinds of
    sense content that are their objects.
  • The point of these acts is to serve as a starting
    point (foundation) for empirical knowledge.
  • But sense contents are particulars, the objects
    of some sensings (i.e. acts of sensing).
  • And knowledge is about facts, not particulars.
    (Broadly, it needs a subject-predicate form
    That this object is characterized in some
    particular way.)

6
The dilemma
  • The SD theorist has to choose between
  • Sense contents are particulars, and sensing is
    not knowing.
  • Sensing is a form of knowing facts, not
    particulars, are sensed.
  • Even if she adopts the first, she can still say
    that sensory knowledge is logically dependent on
    sensings.
  • But SD theorists typically want to have their
    cake and eat it too.
  • This can be done, with a little slippery move
  • To sense a sense content is to sense it as having
    a certain character.
  • When we sense a content as having a certain
    character, we know that it has that character.
  • When we sense a sense content, we can say now
    that we know it, without specifying the character
    we sense it as having.

7
Acquaintance
  • This line gets comfort from the familiar fact
    that we often do speak of knowing particulars, as
    in I know Fred.
  • But the proposal before us links this to
    non-inferential knowledge by the brute force of a
    contextual definition To know x (where x is a
    sense content) just is to know that x has some
    character.
  • Sometimes this is ignored in accounts of the
    givenness of sense contents but if sensings are
    analyzable, we can recover the link to knowledge
    if the analysis matches that of non-inferential
    knowledge of some sensed fact about the sense
    content.

8
The given part
  • Descriptive accounts of sense contents have to
    smuggle this link back inAgain, Sellars rejects
    any reduction of the normative to the
    descriptive.
  • The main point here is that the sensing of sense
    contents is not taken to require any learning,
    setting up of associations, etc. It is a
    primitive epistemic capacity built into us at the
    outset.
  • As primitive, it is the starting point for the
    rest of our knowledge Knowledge is acquired
    first in this form, and then extended to wider
    sorts of knowledge

9
But categorization is acquired
  • Theres a strong tendency in the field to regard
    knowledge that x is Y requires learning to tell
    Ys from non-Ys, the acquisition of the concept
    of a Y, perhaps even the use of symbols for Yness
    other components of this bit of knowledge.
  • The triad
  • A. x senses red sense content s entails x
    non-inferentially knows s is red.
  • B. The ability to sense sense contents is
    unacquired.
  • C. The ability to know facts of the form x is ?
    is acquired.

10
The SD theorists choices
  • Give up the first (A). Sensings now can be
    involved in knowings, but they arent really
    knowledge themselves.
  • Give up the second. Now sensings arent really an
    account of sensations, which we can have without
    learning
  • Give up the third. This is to give up the
    nominalist proclivities of the empiricist
    tradition.

11
The diagnosis
  • Sensings look to be a mongrel concept combining
    ideas about sensations (states that play a
    critical role in sensory knowledge and are
    possible states for us from the outset, but are
    not knowings in themselves) with ideas about
    non-inferential knowings that are at the heart of
    our empirical knowledge about the world around
    us.

12
Sources of the confusion
  • A scientific explanation of the facts of
    perception (and misperception) justifies the
    postulation of inner states that are normally
    brought about by objects with various sensible
    characters under normal conditions. But there is
    nothing epistemic about such states their role,
    thus far, is causal.

13
Second source
  • The argument from security If our knowledge of
    particular matters of fact starts with the things
    we normally report as observations (this is red,
    thats triangular, etc.) then it starts with
    commitments some of which are false there is no
    mark we can introspect that separates the
    veridical ones from the non-veridical. This
    seems to undermine the very idea of empirical
    knowledge.

14
The slide
  • looks or seems talk has an apparent advantage
    here. If we want certainty, we can retreat (by
    degrees), getting
  • There is an object over there thats red and
    triangular on the facing side.
  • There is an object over there that looks red and
    triangulary on the facing side.
  • There looks to be an object over there thats red
    and triangular on the facing side.
  • Each is increasingly secure the last seems
    almost perfectly so.

15
Describing the inner states
  • Now it becomes tempting to take the third of
    these as a description of ones inner state (its
    the sort of state normally produced by objects
    that are red and triangular on the facing side).
  • And this state is harder to be fooled about (its
    more intimately linked to our faculty of
    judgment than the properties of an external
    object).
  • Further, it just doesnt make sense to talk about
    an unveridical sensation.
  • Heres the key mis-step This implies that they
    arent part of the space of reasons at all (they
    are causal- we simply have sensations, i.e. they
    occur in us and that all). Making them the
    foundation of knowledge takes a position, rather
    than report what is given to us.

16
The sense-datum code
  • If we introduce sense datum talk as a code for
    seems talk, we need to be very careful not to
    treat the code as though it were a language
    with internal logical structure that we can
    unpack to identify theoretical commitments.
  • The inferences we make in a sense-datum code must
    follow those that are allowed when the code is
    translated back into the language it is code for.
  • Theories are not just codes they are proper
    languages, which add content to the assertions
    they are linked to by bridge rules.

17
A successful code
  • If the illuminates our understanding of knowledge
    and ordinary things, its because it leads us to
    recognize that in fact we can trade in talk of
    ordinary objects for seems talk in its most
    non-commital sense There looks to be
  • Then ordinary things turn out to be
    constructions out of lookings or appearings.
  • But this is untenable, says Sellars

18
The Logic of looks
  • Is looks a relation (between the subject, a
    thing and a quality in x looks ? to s)?
  • Broad something elliptical must be before our
    minds when a round penny looks elliptical.
    Sense data (which have the characters things look
    to have) are an explanation of such appearings.
  • Some resist such analyses, though, saying that
    there need be nothing red involved when something
    looks red to someone.
  • Sellars starts here with the point that, when we
    say something looks red, we seem to be using red
    in the familiar way, as a property of some
    external objects.

19
Logical priority
  • For Sellars, being red is logically prior to
    looking red.
  • So we cant analyze is red in terms of
    looks-red.
  • But X is red iff X would look red to normal
    perceivers under normal conditions is
    necessarily true. If this isnt an analysis of
    is red in terms of looks-red, what is it?
  • For Sellars, looks is not a relation (or, its
    a relation if you like to say so, but we
    shouldnt assumed the inferences that would
    follow with other relation words go through for
    looks).

20
The tie shop
  • Another vivid example here, of how someone who
    has ordinary colour concepts can come to learn to
    use looks talk.
  • John learns to say it looks green rather than
    it is green (and it looks to be blue rather
    than it is blue).
  • But what hes learned to report is not a new kind
    of fact about the world.
  • What does it looks green report?

21
Experiences and propositions
  • When I report, I see that that is green, I dont
    just report an experience I commit to (endorse)
    a claim closely related to the experience.
  • This is to apply the concept of truth to the
    experience.
  • When I say, instead, I seem to see that that is
    green, I report the experience but I withhold the
    commitment to truth.
  • One experience can be a seeing that x is green
    an intrisically similar experience can be merely
    a seeing that x looks green.
  • See that and looks talk both make the issue
    of endorsement explicit.

22
What looks come to
  • To say that x looks green to s is to say that x
    is having an experience which, if endorsed, we
    would report by saying s sees x to be green.
  • But this makes the difference between normal
    reports and looks talk a matter of backing
    away from commitments that would normally be
    associated with the experience being had.
  • And it puts in doubt the view that looks talk
    is a way of describing the experience itself.

23
Explaining the link
  • Now we can explain the connection between looks
    talk and is talk.
  • X is ? iff X would look ? to standard observers
    in standard conditions is necessary because
    standard conditions are conditions under which
    things look as they are to standard observers.
  • These conditions are only vaguely specified, but
    thats the way it is with ordinary talk
  • This undermines logical atomism, the idea that
    basic concepts are all fundamentally independent
    of each other. On this view we need a lot of
    other concepts (pertaining to standard
    conditions, in particular) before we can have
    (e.g.) colour concepts.

24
Conditions for knowledge
  • We dont have even these very basic empirical
    concepts, for Sellars, unless we can not only
    report accurately (this is green, that is red,
    etc.) but are also aware of, and able to detect
    and report, the conditions under which such
    spontaneous reports are reliable.
  • Logical atomists can move to sense data reports
    to defend their position. But their commitment
    to sense contents is not supported by anything in
    Sellars treatment of looks talk, so these folk
    will have to haul their own water if they want to
    defend this position.

25
Looking red
  • Can we go from somethings looking red to there
    being something red that were aware of?
  • First challenge Univocity. The red things look
    to have is the very red some things do have so
    to say that its a sense content that is red
    when something looks red to us is peculiar
    sense contents are very different from physical
    objects, but this line forces on them all the
    sensible properties we ordinarily attribute to
    physical things.

26
Explanations
  • If we want to explain why x looks red to s, we
    can often do it by saying, well, s is in C
    circumstances, and x is orange, and in C
    circumstances orange things look red.
  • But we can give other sorts of explanation, which
    bring us closer to the heart of sense content and
    sense data talk.
  • Such an explanation would focus on sensations
    (the inner postulated entities Sellars has
    already accepted). But this makes the most
    non-theoretical items (for sense-data theorists)
    into theoretical items, driving the wedge too
    early.

27
A more sympathetic account
  • Experiences can have shared propositional
    contents that receive varying degrees of
    endorsement (full all the way to none at all).
  • The shared content of all these is the
    descriptive content of this account of an
    experience.
  • But looks talk only specifies this description
    of our experience indirectly (as in, if conds
    were standard, it would be a seeing that x is
    red).
  • So we have an open question What is the shared
    intrinsic character of these experiences?

28
Invoking red talk
  • The obvious trick here is to invoke talk of red
    to describe this content.
  • But we need to separate red from physical things
    to do this.
  • Here we run into the familiar analogy Sellars has
    already invoked in other papers.
  • The red of experiences here is not the red of
    physical things, but it is analogous to it.
  • Some try to avoid this by separating things from
    their surfaces, and invoking wild surfaces in
    cases of mere looking.
  • But we dont really think things have surfaces
    as this two-dimensional, detachable account
    proposes.

29
Impressions and Ideas Logical Concerns
  • Ings and eds An experience is often thought
    of as a process that occurs in us this is an
    experiencing, the having of an experience.
  • But experiences are also thought of in terms of
    what is experienced in them (the object of the
    experience).
  • Sellars is concerned here that we not move too
    quickly from a description of an experiencing to
    conclusions about what it is that is experienced
    in that experiencing.
  • In particular, what he calls the common (
    shared) descriptive component of our
    descriptions of experiences may well not be what
    is experienced for instance, if a red item is
    part of this CDC, we may not in fact have
    experienced anything red.

30
Names, labels etc.
  • So the question arises Do we really have a name
    for such experiences?
  • What about of here? Cant we describe these
    experiencings as experiences of red? Cant we
    add sensation talk here, and talk about
    sensations of red?
  • An objection if red is always properly read
    as a property of physical objects, an experience
    or sensation of red demands something red just as
    much as a red experience would.
  • But the of we use in talk of ideas, the
    intentional of, doesnt imply the existence of
    the thing an idea is of (nor does believes in)
  • This logical feature shared by sensation of and
    believes in does not require further parallels
    between sensation talk and intentional contexts.
  • And this is despite the fact that historically
    the assimilation of sensations to ideas was
    widely endorsed.

31
Objective existence
  • So for Descartes and many other early moderns,
    just as red was said to have objective
    existence in the idea of a red triangle, it was
    also said to have objective existence in the
    sensation (or impression, in Humes terminology)
    of a red triangle.
  • Sensations were simply thought of as more
    detailed and specific than the abstract
    thoughts we form.
  • But this is clearly a mistake, and the
    non-extensionality that makes it tempting does
    not give us any real argument for it.

32
Still looking
  • So were still looking for an intrinsic
    description/label for these experiences.
  • But historically many have taken the view that
    this is just wrong-headed we know exactly what
    kind of experience this is, through our
    privileged inner awareness of it.
  • This leads to the problem of other minds, of
    course.
  • But its also a clear instance of the given
    this time, what is said to be given is the
    kinds to which our sensations belong.

33
Two questions
  • How do we become aware of the sorts that our
    experiences fall under?
  • How do we communicate/share the categories each
    of us has for their experiences?
  • The view Sellars is criticizing here thinks the
    given is an answer to the first, and accepts
    that there is no answer to the second.
  • This answer to the first assumes that our
    awareness of the sorts under which our
    experiences are to be classified is given, a
    feature of immediate experience.
  • Recall here Sellars earlier invocation of the
    empiricist notion that all categorization of
    items under sorts requires learning.

34
Universals, repeatables and determinables
  • For Sellars a universal is a repeatable (this is
    the std. view today).
  • Thus even a very specific/determinate sort of
    experience (my current visual fields character,
    for instance) can be a universal, since this
    arrangement of colours etc. can be repeated in a
    later experience.
  • But the tradition (Locke et al.) thought of
    universals as generic, i.e. as abstracting from
    these details, and passed over the problem of
    repeatables to focus on the formation of such
    more general ideas. (Note the nice discussion of
    the need for both conjunctive and disjunctive
    ideas to cope with the phenomena here.)

35
The key point again
  • LBH all agree that merely by having sensations we
    have the idea of determinate repeatables or
    sorts.
  • A nominalist alternative suppose we think of
    the awareness of a red sensation as the awareness
    of a red particular, rather than as the awareness
    of its being red.
  • Then the formation of ideas of repeatables would
    proceed by the association of words (red) with
    a range of resembling particulars.
  • But the association needs to be handled
    carefully If we think of it as grounded on a
    prior awareness of the particulars as resembling
    or even as red then the myth of the given rises
    again.
  • If we instead reject these, and simply say that
    it is the group of particulars that is associated
    with the word, then we get a kind of nominalism
    it is only from the later point of view, where we
    have a language in which to pick out classes of
    resembling particulars, that we are aware of
    their resemblance before that, all we have are a
    range of patterns of response that we can be
    trained in.

36
The upshot
  • This is not Sellars nominalism its pretty
    crude, really.
  • But it does break the link between sensations and
    thought-contents, freeing up the direct
    perception account according to which words are
    directly linked to the external world and its
    features, not to our sensations or impressions.
  • The essential causal role of red sensations is
    not undermined by this but it is not an
    inferential role in which our awareness of the
    immediately available redness of some
    sensations provides the facts and ideas out of
    which we somehow arrive at the idea of redness as
    a feature of physical things.

37
The logic of means
  • The object here is to provide more material for
    Sellars psychological nominalism, the view that
    we have no awareness of logical space prior
    to/independent of learning a language.
  • But Sellars rejects the crudely associative view
    of how words are linked to the things they apply
    to.
  • On this view, red means what it does because it
    has the syntax (grammar) of a predicate and is
    a response to red things.
  • This isnt nearly enough (its too atomistic) for
    Sellars.
  • But it wouldnt even be tempting if it werent
    for the naïve word-world view of means contexts.

38
Recalling BBK
  • Here we find points familiar from BBK means
    for Sellars invokes translation (and a rich
    normative parallel between the two items joined
    by means as in Rot (in German) means red.)
  • This covers the ground in a way that the more
    common view cannot, since it equates the force of
    means in
  • Und means and.
  • Rot means red.

39
Simple association is not enough
  • So the mere invocation of means contexts does
    not generate a theory of how a word comes to play
    a role sufficiently similar to that of another
    for us to say that they have the same meaning.
  • In fact, this standard is rich and flexible
    translation is a complex art, and its demands
    vary with our communicative aims/concerns
  • In particular, understanding red requires quite
    a bit more than the grammar of a predicate and an
    association with red things. Linguistic
    thermometers are not enough to capture meanings.

40
Foundations
  • A foundation for empirical knowledge, for
    Sellars, is a pretty specific thing.
  • The myth requires that the foundation be facts
    that are
  • Non-inferentially known.
  • Such that knowledge of them presupposes no other
    knowledge.
  • Such that all knowledge of empirical matters of
    fact is ultimately decided by reference to
    knowledge of these foundational facts.

41
Something emphasized
  • Some argue that, if a piece of knowledge depends
    on having some other knowledge, it must in fact
    depend on inference in some way.
  • For Sellars this is a mistake, and its part of
    the myth. The kind of dependence that his holism
    invokes does not make all our knowledge a product
    of inference.
  • But it does make its content dependent on our
    grasping its inferential relations to other
    claims.

42
Details
  • Observation reports seem to have authority,
    without being inferred from other claims we
    already believe.
  • How shall we understand this authority?
  • One key is the link between reports and
    circumstances.
  • This point turns on the distinction between
    fact-stating uses of sentences and report-making
    uses.

43
Token-reflexives
  • Words like here, now, this or that are
    token-reflexive they link up to their
    circumstances of utterance in ways that lead the
    same sentence to make different assertions in
    different circumstances.
  • Tensed verbs have much the same effect, since
    they are tied to times of utterance too.
  • Reports regularly, though not necessarily, make
    use of these sorts of linguistic device to link
    the report made to the circumstances it is a
    report about.
  • A report must have some kind of direct link to
    the circumstances it reports about
  • Fact-stating doesnt depend on circumstances in
    the same way.

44
Two sources of credibility
  • Some sentence tokens are credible because they
    are tokens of a type all tokens of which have
    authority.
  • But some sentence tokens are credible because of
    how they are linked to the circumstances in which
    a token is produced The token came to be
    through a certain process under certain
    circumstances.

45
Authority for sentence types
  • Sellars says some sentence types are
    intrinsically authoritative some analytic
    sentences belong to this group.
  • Some get authority by inferential links to
    others.
  • But empirical knowledge will not reduce (without
    some residue) to these two groups. (No empirical
    sentence type has intrinsic authority, and
    inferential links to such wont do the trick
    either.)
  • So we need sentence types whose authority comes
    from tokens that are produced in the right way
    and in the right circumstances.

46
The flow of credibility
  • These two sources of credibility flow in opposite
    directions
  • Credibility for analytic sentences flows from
    types to their tokens, and then via inference to
    some other sentence types.
  • Credibility for observation sentences flows from
    tokens to types, and then again via inference to
    other sentence types.

47
Sellars on Empiricist Dogmas
  • Conflating the authority of analytic and
    observational sentences An attempt at a unified
    theory of credibility leads to trouble.
  • The idea is to appeal to rules just as the rules
    for using the concepts in an analytic sentence
    ensure that it must be true, the rules for using
    the language involved in an observation report
    are such that, if they are followed when the
    report is made, the observation report is true.

48
Prefatory points
  • Reports can be thought of as stripped of their
    action and interpersonal aspectsa mere,
    spontaneous thinking that p can be a report.
  • But thinking of them as actions has influenced
    the tradition here, which construes the rightness
    of a report as a special case of the rightness of
    actions (under some system of rules).
  • When we think of them this way, we have to
    construe them as deliberate followings of these
    rules (otherwise the rule is a mere
    regularity).
  • That is, we have to judge that the circumstances
    were such that the rule requires the report and
    make the report for that reason.

49
The given again
  • This leads directly to the given again, since
    these observation-actions are correct only when
    they are made in the course of following a rule,
    which requires that we be able to judge that the
    circumstances are such that the rule
    requires/endorses the report.
  • Such judgments depend on a primitive awareness of
    the matters of fact necessary to apply the rules
    for using these words.
  • Recall that we are talking here about the
    foundational judgments that are at the root of
    all empirical knowledge so there is no escape...

50
But is there a way out?
  • Begin with mere reliable reporting the
    thermometer account.
  • Now, can we extend this to cover something more
    properly like knowledge?
  • The key question is authoritybut authority for
    what?
  • Actions are not what we need here mere behaviour
    of a type that its reasonable to endorse is
    enough (action presupposes too much
    deliberateness here).

51
Being a knower
  • The key, however, is the subjects own ability to
    recognize that she is in a position of authority
    with respect to such reports.
  • That is, she must be in a position to recognize
    that she is a standard observer in standard
    conditions, so that her inclination to report
    this is green is indeed reliable.
  • This requires quite sophisticated conceptual
    grasp of the place of such reports in the world
  • It also seems to require a kind of induction.

52
The threat of a regress
  • The idea is that to make a report that expresses
    observational knowledge, one would have to know
    that such overt verbal performances are reliable
    indicators of the facts reported.
  • And this means that all observational knowledge
    depends on a fair bit of knowledge that. In
    fact, we need to know things like X is a
    reliable symptom of Y.
  • So observations dont stand on their own feet
    individually.
  • Worse, it seems to run counter to the empiricist
    notion that the sort of general knowledge we have
    when we know X is a reliable symptom of Y depends
    on having a lot of knowledge of particular cases
    where X is correlated with Y.

53
Responding to the regress
  • This seems to be a regress- before we can
    actually know, by observation, that we have a
    case of Y, we need to know that X is a reliable
    symptom of Y.
  • But we need to know cases of Y (and cases of X)
    to justify the claim that X is a reliable
    symptom of Y. OUCH!
  • But when we classify an episode or event as a
    case of knowing, we are locating it in a
    normative space. Its possible to establish the
    normative status of an episode retrospectively.
    The regress dissolves (p. 169).

54
Rejecting the foundation
  • Sellars rejects the idea of observational
    responses that are both direct and immediate.
  • Such observations would be self-authenticating,
    that is, they would stand on their own but they
    are, at root, non-verbal, internal episodes.
  • And this authority is transmitted to linguistic
    acts (reports) because of an awareness of the
    rules governing how these episodes are to be
    characterized in words.
  • Once we have the force of these episodes cast in
    linguistic terms, inference connects them to
    other sentences, so that these episodes become
    the foundation for all our empirical knowledge.

55
Launching the constructive phase
  • The point of the rest of the paper is to explain
    Sellars own views on the nature and role of
    inner episodes.
  • The sense in which they are non-verbal does not
    (says Sellars) lend any support to the idea of
    the given.
  • But Sellars rejection of this particular view of
    the foundation of empirical knowledge is not a
    rejection of the broader idea that there are
    observation-reporting sentences that serve as the
    touchstone for empirical knowledge. It is aimed
    at the idea of the given (which is related to the
    demand that the foundation be locked in and
    independent of any other knowledge).
  • The active element of self-correction is crucial
    here.

56
Philosophy of science
  • Sellars is concerned about the effects of
    specialization in particular, the recognition of
    philosophy of science as a distinct
    specialization in philosophy.
  • The worry seems to be that specialization may
    lead other philosophers to leave science to the
    philosophers of science, and lose track of the
    need for all philosophers to respond to the
    development of the scientific world view.
  • Science is the flowering of an aspect of
    discourse that is part of the ordinary world
    view, and which may be lost sight of if we dont
    attend to science and how it works in our
    philosophical thinking.

57
Evaluation
  • To evaluate features of our conceptual frameworks
    requires an appreciation of science as revealing
    standards of evaluation and alternative
    frameworks that may well do better in terms of
    those standards.
  • This needs care the tendency to say things like
    physical objects are not really coloured is a
    confused way of recognizing that a framework that
    includes such objects has deficiencies that are
    put right in a different framework, now under
    construction in the scientific enterprise.
  • On these questions, science is the measure.

58
The given as a barrier here
  • If we take some aspect of the manifest image as
    given then this kind of critique is blocked a
    framework anchored in the given is one were
    stuck with (we can alter it in various ways, but
    the basics are fixed).
  • This anchor is sometimes thought of as an
    ostensive tie linking the concepts of the
    framework to a aspect of reality. But consider
    the oddity of the idea of an inner ostension.
  • This goes with the idea that science is not a
    complete framework in its own right, but a mere
    auxiliary.

59
As if
  • The suggestion is that the unquestionable nature
    of the given locks us into any framework that
    it arises in.
  • The upshot is that an alternative framework which
    outperforms the given framework must be treated
    in terms of as if, that is, the things of the
    given framework can be thought of as behaving as
    if some other framework were true but we can
    never dispense with the given framework in favour
    of this new (and superior) one.

60
The other error
  • The other barrier to what Sellars sees to a
    correct appreciation of the scientific framework
    is the reification of a methodological
    distinction between theoretical and
    non-theoretical discourse into a substantive
    distinction.
  • The contrast
  • Science as a peninsular offshoot of ordinary
    discourse vs.
  • Science as an expression of a fundamental aspect
    of discourse which is central and ultimately
    transformative.

61
Private episodes
  • We still have no take on how it is that the
    experience that is a seeing that x over there is
    green is similar to one that is merely a seeing
    that x over there looks green.
  • Two routes
  • Introduce inner episodes as theoretical posits
    and develop an account of the similarity within
    that theory.
  • Posit these similarities as given.
  • The second is now ruled out, so we need to turn
    to the first, however peculiar it may seem.

62
Applying the critique of the given
  • red etc. apply to physical objects first, so
    while we tend to describe these experiences using
    such words, this use of those words cannot be
    univocal.
  • If we just use these words to link the
    experiences to standard occasions on which such
    experiences occur, then we have a definite
    description of such experiences that picks them
    out, but nothing to say about what they are
    really like.
  • To be able to notice a certain kind of thing (as
    being of that kind) is already to have a concept
    of that kind of thing. (176)
  • One central puzzle The combination of privacy
    (only I can report my inner states) with
    intersubjectivity (others can know about them in
    other ways/ inferentially). Sellars says we can
    have both!
  • But before dealing with sensations, Sellars turns
    to consider thoughts.

63
Thoughts
  • Even if we take the view that thoughts are
    linguistic, the number of cases where overt
    linguistic behaviour accompanies behaviour that
    it seems to explain is too few the sorts of
    behaviour that we explain in terms of thoughts
    are often unaccompanied by any overt linguistic
    behaviour.
  • And when that behaviour is not habitual (more or
    less automatic), we can hardly resist invoking
    thoughts to explain it.
  • The classical account holds that there are inner
    episodes called thoughts, and linguistic
    behaviours are meaningful insofar as they express
    those thoughts. Further, these episodes are
    introspectible and even transparent (self-
    revealing/ known whenever they are had).

64
The core of the notion
  • We each have a stream of these inner episodes.
  • We have privileged, but not infallible or
    complete, access to them.
  • They occur, sometimes, without overt verbal
    behaviour.
  • We dont need a performance to be going on that
    we perceive inwardly here.
  • Thoughts are a sort of linguistic episode, that
    is, they are modeled on over speech.

65
The Ryleans
  • Here we imagine our ancestors, speaking a
    somewhat limited language.
  • The language describes external objects in terms
    of their sensible features.
  • Sellars also supposes that it has semantic
    concepts so they can speak of meanings (read
    in terms of the roles of words phrases)
  • The aim is to explore how a language like this
    can come to have the means to talk of inner
    episodes.

66
On semantics again
  • The force of semantic talk includes implications
    about the typical causes and effects of certain
    utterances.
  • But it is not exhausted by these implications.
  • More importantly here, having semantical talk
    allows us to say a lot of things about utterances
    that are also commonly said about thoughts (that
    they are about, or refer to, something, etc.)
  • We could try, then, to capture thoughts just by
    appeal to a conditional/hypothetical link to
    overt language and its semantics.

67
The Alternative?
  • Inner episodes (rather than conditional/hypothetic
    al speech).
  • The classical notion also makes these episodes
    the primary vehicles of meaning but Sellars will
    reject this aspect of the classical view.
  • So the challenge is to combine a speech first
    view of meaning with an account of thoughts as
    real inner episodes.

68
Theories and Models
  • Here we encounter the philosophy of science
    again, which Sellars will draw on to explain his
    view of the status of these inner episodes.
  • We typically develop a theory by positing certain
    entities and certain postulates about how they
    behave.
  • These are then linked to some observable
    phenomena (regularities or empirical laws) in
    effect, we propose that the phenomena are as they
    are because they involve these items in a certain
    way.
  • But in fact theories are typically developed in a
    very different way.
  • We generally draw on known behaviours of familiar
    objects (waves, for example), and present these
    as a model of what is going on with respect to
    some phenomena.
  • Such models are qualified (we dont propose that
    electromagnetic waves are just like waves in
    water, but that they are similar in some
    respects, while different in others.)

69
Continuity
  • Further, common-sense is not limited to
    induction. (Unlike the idealized MI, it can
    invoke postulated entities too and for Sellars,
    the MI does contain fossilized posits, despite
    its limitation to inductive methods.)
  • So our Ryleans will have the ability to develop
    postulational explanations for similarities and
    differences in the behaviour of physical things.

70
Behaviourism
  • Note that this was a major influence in
    psychology when Sellars was writing EPM.
  • Sellars rejects narrow forms of behaviourism,
    while being perfectly happy with methodological
    behaviourism.
  • This does not require that psychological concepts
    be analyzable into behavioural terms, but only
    that assertions in our new, scientific
    psychological language be justified by
    behavioural evidence.
  • So, while we introduce these concepts by means of
    their links to behaviour, we do not suppose that
    their meaning is exhausted by this link to
    behaviour they can be fully fledged theoretical
    concepts.

71
Expectations
  • Of course we expect any such theory to link up to
    our physiological understanding of the nervous
    system and its role in behaviour.
  • But this does not mean that the behaviourists
    concepts are physiological at the outset
  • It does mean that our concepts are both linked to
    behaviour and linked to our expectations of how
    they will fit in with other aspects of our
    understanding of the world.

72
Back to Jones
  • Jones proposes a theory of inner episodes,
    modeled on overt speech.
  • These explain intelligent behaviour that goes on
    even when no overt commentary accompanies it.
  • The episodes carry the semantic force of the
    speech acts they are modeled on.
  • And they are taken as the real, proximate
    causes of intelligent behaviour, even when
    accompanied by an overt explanatory discourse.
  • Think here of how we accompany demonstration with
    commentary when instructing people in how to do
    something

73
More details
  • The commentary follows, explaining the parallels
    between speech and thought and where the two
    differ.
  • One important point Nothing in the theory
    requires that we have thoughts first and language
    second the ability to have thoughts may depend
    on learning a language.
  • Another The theory does not imply that thoughts
    are the truly semantic items, with utterances
    only semantic in a derivative sense, as
    expressing certain thoughts.
  • Finally, these inner episodes need not be
    construed as immediate experiences no perceptual
    model of them is implied here.

74
Introspection
  • Having been taught to use this theory, people
    find that they can sometimes report their
    thoughts without relying on the overt behavioural
    evidence others need to reach the same
    conclusion.
  • Now the theoretical language has a reporting
    role, and its one that recognizes a kind of
    privileged access.
  • But the concepts involved are still public, and
    their link to behaviour is still part of their
    meaning so the privacy involved here is not
    absolute or incorrigible.

75
Inner perceptual episodes
  • Now were ready for Jones second theory inner
    episodes modeled on the perceptible features of
    objects, which are invoked to explain illusions
    and related perceptual phenomena.
  • This provides us with a theory in which we really
    do have a description of the inner episode that
    is the same when we see a red triangle, see a
    triangle that looks red, see something that looks
    like a red triangle and merely seem to see a red
    triangle.
  • The price, of course, is to accept that these
    inner states are postulated, not given.

76
Details
  • These are episodes (goings-on) not particulars.
  • They should not be construed in
    perceptual/epistemological terms The model is
    not, a seeing of a red triangle but a red
    triangular surface.
  • In general, we have the occurrence of inner
    replicas a matter of a description of whats
    going on in us, not normative matter at all.
  • The terms the theory provides give us a
    substantive description of these states, rather
    than the mere definite descriptions used so far.

77
The content of the description
  • The content of the description is a matter of the
    theoretical language and the inferences it
    supports.
  • Thus we know that the relations of compatibility,
    incompatibility, etc. grounded in the ways
    objects sensible properties can be arranged are
    shared by these theoretical predicates describing
    our impressions/sensations.
  • But the limits of the parallel are not clearly
    specified yet, and can be worked out/explored in
    a pretty open-ended way.

78
Contentless form?
  • Sellars objects to the view that such concepts
    (characterized by their internal inferential
    relations and by a link to certain
    observational circumstances) are themselves
    contentless.
  • For him they are no more contentless than any
    other theoretical predicate,
  • And the view that all such predicates are formal/
    contentless is a part of the myth of the given
    (according to which only the predicates that are
    part of the given have real (ostensive) content.

79
Expectations
  • What is the relation between these states of
    perceivers and physiological models of ourselves?
  • In the long run we expect them to fit together,
    giving a physiological account of these states.
  • But our present physiology does not have the
    resources to do this (homogeneity again).
  • And Sellars doesnt believe that the physics of
    non-living things has the resources either
    something unique to organisms (ones sufficiently
    like us) needs to turn upwe need a micro theory
    of sentient organisms, he says, to find the
    micro-states corresponding to these posited molar
    states.

80
The tradition and the sequel
  • The modern view that objects arent really
    coloured, and colour is in the mind of the
    perceiver, is a confusion of this scientific
    anticipation with a feature of the manifest
    image.
  • The upshot of Jones work is that we have a
    notion of both thoughts and impressions that
    allows introspection (individuals are the
    reporters for their own states) but also makes
    the link with observable behaviour (and thus
    training by our linguistic seniors as we grow up)
    part of the meaning of this language.

81
The order of things
  • The language of impressions is no more the result
    of antecedent noticings of impressions than the
    language of molecules is the result of antecedent
    noticings of molecules.
  • The phenomenologist, in describing these states,
    fails to recognize her own creative role
  • She takes herself to be analyzing human knowledge
    as it already was, when she is actually
    contributing to an entirely new body of knowledge
    whose projected links to a scientific
    micro-theory of sentient organisms point towards
    a unified science including impressions.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com