Mathematical Paradoxes - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 51
About This Presentation
Title:

Mathematical Paradoxes

Description:

It is easier to first calculate the probability that all n birthdays are different. ... Banach-Tarski paradox is the famous 'doubling the ball' paradox, which states ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:846
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 52
Provided by: Mathematic91
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Mathematical Paradoxes


1
Mathematical Paradoxes
  • That which is true is not always obvious.
  • That which is obvious is not always true.

2
Definition (from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia)
  • A paradox (Gk pa??d????, "aside belief") is an
    apparently true statement or group of statements
    that leads to a contradiction or a situation
    which defies intuition.
  • Three types of paradoxes
  • False Proofs
  • Unexpected Facts
  • Logical Dilemmas

3
Unexpected facts or veridical paradoxes
  • Results appears unrealistic.
  • Results are correct.
  • Results can be proven true.

4
Examples
  • The birthday paradox
  • How many people must there be in a room to that
    states that the probability of having two or more
    people with the same birth date is 50?
  • How about 90?
  • How about 99.99996?
  • How about 100?

5
Probability results
  • For 23 or more people, Probability gt 50.
  • For 60 or more people, Probability gt 99.
  • For 100 or more people Probability gt 99.9996.
  • For 366 or more people, Probability 100.

6
The Proof
  • It is easier to first calculate the probability ?
    that all n birthdays are different. If n
    365, it is given by
  • because the second person cannot have the same
    birthday as the first with probability (364/365),
    the third cannot have the same birthday as the
    first two (363/365), etc.
  • The event of at least two of the n persons having
    the same birthday is complementary to all n
    birthdays being different. Therefore, its
    probability p(n) is

7
The Graph
8
Another Paradox
  • The Monty Hall Paradox

9
The Monty Hall problem
  • Suppose you're on a game show, and you're given
    the choice of three doors Behind one door is a
    new automobile behind the others, nominal
    prizes. You pick a door, say No. 3, and the host,
    who knows what's behind each door, opens one of
    the other doors, say No. 2, which has a lesser
    prize. He then says to you, "Do you want to pick
    door No. 1 or do you want to keep your original
    choice?"
  • Is it to your advantage to switch your choice?

10
Answer
  • YES! It is to your advantage to switch doors.
  • Why? Because you double your chances of winning
    the automobile.
  • The probability the automobile is behind door
    number 1 is 2/3.
  • The probability it is behind door 3 is 1/3.

11
Justification
  • For i 1,2,3 let MiMonty picks door i,
    CiContestant picks door i, and AiAuto is
    behind door i.
  • Assumptions Ai and Cj are independent events
    with P(Ai) P(Cj) 1/3 for all i, j.
  • As in the original problem, the Contestant picked
    door 3 and Monty picked Door 2.
  • Since Monty knows where the car is we have
    P(M2A1?C3) 1, P(M2A2?C3) 0, P(M2A3?C3)
    1/2.
  • We want to findP(A1M2?C3) and compare it to
    P(A3M2?C3).

12
A Little Probability Theory
  • P(M2?C3) P(A1?M2?C3) P(A2?M2?C3)
    P(A3?M2?C3) (by the law of total probability)
    P(M2A1?C3)P(A1 ?C3)P(M2A2?C3)P(A2 ?C3)
    P(M2A3?C3)P(A3 ?C3) (conditional
    probabilities) 1?P(A1 ?C3) 0?P(A2 ?C3)
    (1/2)?P(A3 ?C3) 1?(1/9) 0 (1/2)?(1/9)
    (1/6).
  • Probability that auto is behind door 1 given
    M2?C3 P(A1M2?C3) P(A1?M2?C3)/P(M2?C3)
    P(M2A1?C3)P(A1 ?C3 )/P(M2?C3) (Bayes Theorem)
    1?(1/9)/(1/6) 2/3.
  • Probability that auto is behind door 3 given
    M2?C3 P(A3M2?C3) P(A3?M2?C3)/P(M2?C3)
    P(M2A3?C3)P(A3 ?C3 )/P(M2?C3)
    (1/2)?(1/9)/(1/6) 1/3.

13
Sometimes questions seem too simple
  • Another Paradox

14
Boy or Girl
  • The Boy or Girl problem is a well-known example
    in probability theory
  • In a two-child family the older child is a boy.
    What is the probability that the younger child is
    a girl?
  • In a two-child family one of the children is a
    boy. What is the probability that the other
    child is a girl?

15
Answer to question 1
  • Assuming boy and girls are equally likely and the
    outcome of the second pregnancy is independent of
    the first, the probability that the second child
    is a girl is ½.

16
Answer to question 2
  • Assuming boy and girls are equally likely and the
    outcome of the second pregnancy is independent of
    the first, the probability that the other child
    is a girl is 2/3.

17
Justification
  • There are four possible combinations of children.
    Labeling boys B and girls G, and using the first
    letter to represent the older child, the sample
    space is
  • (B,B), (B,G), (G,B), (G,G).
  • Under the assumptions, the above four
    possibilities are equally likely.
  • Since it is known that there is a boy in the
    family, only the first three events are under
    consideration.
  • Of these 2/3 consist on a family with one boy and
    one girl, so the probability is 2/3.

18
A similar paradox
  • The three card paradox

19
Three Card Problem
  • Suppose you have a deck of 60 cards, consisting
    of
  • 20 black cards that are black on both sides,
  • 20 white cards that are white on both sides, and
  • 20 mixed card that are black on one side and
    white on the other.
  • The cards are shuffled. One is pulled out of the
    deck at random, and placed on a table observing
    only one of the sides. The side facing up is
    black. What is the probability that the other
    side is also black?

20
Answer
  • The probability that the other side is also black
    is 2/3.

21
A Lie Not a Paradox
  • If it appears too good to be true it is probably
    false.

22
The Two Envelopes Problem
  • The puzzle Let's say you are given two
    indistinguishable envelopes, each of which
    contains a positive sum of money. One envelope
    contains twice as much as the other. You may pick
    one envelope and keep whatever amount it
    contains. You pick one envelope at random but
    before you open it you're offered the possibility
    to take the other envelope instead.

23
Now, suppose you reason as follows
  • Denote by A the amount in my selected envelope.
  • The probability that A is the smaller amount is
    1/2, and that it's the larger also ½.
  • The other envelope may contain either 2A or A/2.
  • If A is the smaller amount the other envelope
    contains 2A.
  • If A is the larger amount the other envelope
    contains A/2.
  • Thus, the other envelope contains 2A with
    probability 1/2 and A/2 with probability ½.
  • So the expected value of the money in the other
    envelope is (1/2)(A/2) (1/2)(2A) (5/4)A.
  • This is greater than A, so I gain on average by
    swapping.

24
Follow Up
  • After the switch I can denote that content B and
    reason in exactly the same manner as above.
  • I will conclude that the most rational thing to
    do is to swap back again.
  • To be rational I will thus end up swapping
    envelopes indefinitely.
  • Since we cannot win arbitrarily large amounts
    given the amounts in the two envelopes something
    is wrong with the argument.

25
Explanation
  • The most common way to explain the problem (not a
    paradox) is to observe that A isn't a constant in
    the expected value calculation, step 7 above. In
    the first term A is the smaller amount while in
    the second term A is the larger amount. To mix
    different instances of a variable or parameter in
    the same formula like this shouldn't be
    legitimate, so step 7 is thus the proposed cause
    of the paradox.

26
Paradoxes in Analysis
  • Whats going on here?

27
Tarski paradox
  • Tarski paradox or Hausdorff-Banach-Tarski paradox
    is the famous "doubling the ball" paradox, which
    states that by using the axiom of choice it is
    possible to take a solid ball in 3-dimensional
    space, cut it up into finitely many
    (non-measurable) pieces and, moving them using
    only rotations and translations, reassemble the
    pieces into two balls of the same radius as the
    original.

28
The Hausdorff paradox
  • In mathematics, the Hausdorff paradox, named
    after Felix Hausdorff, states that if you remove
    a certain countable subset of the sphere S², the
    remainder can be divided into three subsets A, B
    and C such that A, B, C and B ?? C are all
    congruent. In particular, it follows that on S²
    there is no "finitely additive measure" defined
    on all subsets such that the measure of congruent
    sets is equal. In other words, one cannot define
    a probability space on the sphere S² which
    preserves congruence.

29
Origins of Probability
  • Marquis de Laplace (1749-1827)
  • Formalized the calculus of probability.
  • Defined the probability p(A) as the ratio of the
    number of events that result in the outcome A to
    the total number of possible events.
  • Coined the term equiprobable.
  • Restrictions Required an experiment to consist
    of a finite number of possible outcomes.

30
Extensions
  • For experiments with an infinite number of
    possible outcomes, results were approximated by
    experimentation.
  • Was not fully endorsed by all mathematicians.
  • One problem that arose was coined Bertrand's
    paradox.

31
The Problem
  • Consider an equilateral triangle inscribed in a
    circle.
  • Suppose a chord of the circle is chosen at
    random.
  • What is the probability that the chord is longer
    than a side of the inscribed triangle?
  • Different mathematicians were simulating this
    experiment with each obtaining different results.

32
The analysis
  • Joseph Louis François Bertrand (March 11, 1822
    April 5, 1900), a French mathematician began to
    analyze the various solution, to formalize the
    approaches and to summarize the results.
  • He presented three techniques for selecting a
    random chord.
  • The "random endpoints" method.
  • The "random radius" method.
  • The "random midpoint" method.
  • The work was named Bertrands Paradox.

33
The "random endpoints" method
  • Randomly choose a point on the circumference of
    the circle.
  • Randomly choose another point on the circle.
  • Draw the chord joining it to the first point.
  • The result is a random chord.

34
The "random radius" method
  • Choose, at random, a radius of the circle.
  • Choose a random point on the radius.
  • Construct the chord whose midpoint is the chosen
    point (such a chord is always perpendicular to
    the radius).
  • The resulting chord is a random chord.

35
The "random midpoint" method
  • Choose a point at random anywhere within the
    circle.
  • Construct a chord with the chosen point as its
    midpoint.
  • The resulting chord is a random chord.

36
The Analysis
  • Bertrands Paradox

37
The random endpoints" method
  • Rotate the triangle so that the first point is at
    one vertex.
  • If the second point is chosen between the
    endpoints of the side opposite the first point,
    the chord is longer than a side of the triangle.

38
Random Endpoints

39
Random Endpoints" method The Answer
  • The length of this arc is one third of the
    circumference of the circle.
  • Therefore the probability a random chord is
    longer than a side of the inscribed triangle is
    1/3.

40
The "random radius" method
  • Rotate the triangle so a side of the equilateral
    triangle is perpendicular to the radius.
  • The cord with the midpoint on the radius will be
    perpendicular to the radius at the chosen point.
  • The chord is longer than a side of the triangle
    if the chosen point on the radius is inside the
    triangle.

41
Random Radius

42
Random Radius" MethodThe Answer
  • Notice that ½ of the radius is inside the
    triangle and ½ is outside.
  • Therefore, the probability that the random ray is
    longer than a side of the inscribed triangle is
    ½.

43
The "random midpoint" method
  • Every chord has only one midpoint.
  • Draw the chord having the randomly chosen point
    as its midpoint.
  • The chord is longer than a side of the inscribed
    triangle if the chosen point falls within a
    concentric circle of radius ½.

44
Random Point

45
Random Midpoint" MethodThe Answer
  • The area of the smaller circle is one fourth the
    area of the larger circle.
  • Therefore the probability a random chord is
    longer than a side of the inscribed triangle is
    1/4.

46
The selection methods can be visualized as
follows. Other than a diameter, a chord is
uniquely identified by its midpoint. Each of the
three selection methods presented above yields a
different distribution of midpoints. Methods 1
and 2 yield two different nonuniform
distributions, while method 3 yields a uniform
distribution.
47
Explanation
  • All answers are correct.
  • What constitutes a random cord within a circle is
    not clear.
  • Once a definition is accepted an appropriate
    method with a definitive answer can be developed.

48
Infinity
  • A problem in itself

49
The Question
  • Are there more Irrational Numbers than Rational
    Numbers?
  • Be careful, if you answer the question you have
    to prove it.

50
Consider the following
  • True or False Between any two rational numbers
    there is always an irrational number.
  • True or False Between any two irrational
    numbers there is always a rational number
  • Both of these statements can be proven true.
  • So, which set has more elements?

51
The End
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com