Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory

1 / 160
About This Presentation
Title:

Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory

Description:

... separated from that of chimpanzees and bonobos, our closest primate relatives. ... adaptations or traits distinguish humans form their nearest primate relatives? ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:71
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 161
Provided by: Psy102

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory


1
Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory
  • There are heritable variations in traits (i.e.,
    either a physical characteristic such as brain
    size, height or a psychological characteristic
    such as sociability, selfishness, generosity,
    aggresiveness and intelligence).
  • In particular environments some traits contribute
    more to an individuals fitness (i.e., survival
    and reproduction) than others.
  • As a result these traits are positively selected
    and increase in frequency. In a word, they
    become adaptations.

2
Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Psychology
  • Human thought, feeling and action reflect
    adaptations or traits that evolved over the past
    5,000,000 years when the human line separated
    from that of chimpanzees and bonobos, our closest
    primate relatives.
  • Adaptations are modular (e.g., vision, language).
    But to what extent? How distinct an entity
    (e.g., lungs vs jealousy vs sociality)?
  • Sociality (i.e., group living), is a key human
    adaptation.
  • The costs and benefits associated with our
    peculiarly extensive and complex networks of
    social relations are the primary source of
    selection pressures on humans.

3
Humans Compared to Chimpanzees and Bonobos
  • What adaptations or traits distinguish humans
    form their nearest primate relatives? What do
    these adaptations imply about human social
    psychology?
  • Large brains
  • Long periods of juvenile dependence
  • Extensive parental care including the transfer of
    vast amounts of information
  • Multigenerational bilateral kin networks

4
(And thats not all! Theres )
  • Habitual bipedal locomotion
  • Cryptic or concealed ovulation
  • Menopause
  • Culture, including language
  • Letal competition among kin-based coaltions
  • N.B. A few other species exhibit some of these
    adaptations. However, only humans possess the
    entire set of them in their most complex form.

5
The Adaptive Value of a Trait Depends on Its
Contribution to Fitness
  • The ultimate and most direct measure of fitness
    is the number of healthy offspring or
    reproductive success (RS). Thus, a traits
    benefits refers to how much it increases RS and
    its costs, how much it decreases RS.
  • We often use less direct or more proximal
    measures of fitness that we assume contribute to
    RS (e.g., as health, strength, wealth) for
    convenience.

6
Why Do We Think Group Living Is an Adaptation?
  • Because it is universal.
  • Because it is typical of species most closely
    related by common descent to humans.
  • Because it has neurophysiological correlates
    (e.g., neocortex ratio and social network
    density ostracism and activation of pain area
    in brain).
  • Because it has affective correlates (e.g.,
    isolation and ostracism are painful and universal
    punishments while being liked and respected are
    pleasurable and universal rewards).
  • Beause it has cognitive correlates (e.g., Theory
    of Mind cheater-detection modules).
  • Because bio-economic analyses of fitness (i.e.,
    benefits to RS relative to it costs) suggests
    living in groups is adaptive.

7
Do species most closely related to humans
(chimps and bonobo) live in groups? Yes. Are
chimp groups and bonobo groups similar? No. So
what?
8
Are there neurophysiological correlates of group
living? Yes. Neocortex size increases with
group size social complexity.
9
Bio-economic Analysis
  • In examining sociality as an adaptive strategy
    Richard Alexander considers the recurrent
    problems faced by groups in the ancestral
    environment and compares the hypothetical fitness
    costs and benefits of increasing group size
    from living with several conspecifics (e.g., in
    separate nuclear families), through a few dozen
    (e.g., nuclear family coalitions or extended
    families), one or two hunderd (hunter-gatherer
    groups), to thousands or millions (towns, cities,
    clans, tribes and nations).

10
The cost/benefit return of increasing groups
size Minimizing home, den or nest site shortages
as an adaptive problem
11
The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing disease as an adaptive problem
12
The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages (when food is widely
distributed, thus, readily found) as an adaptive
problem
13
The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages when food sites are few
and hard to find as an adaptive problem
14
The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages when food is large,
hard to catch animals (prey) as an adaptive
problem
15
The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing the danger of predation
16
  • Protection from predation provides the largest
    benefit to fitness from living in groups during
    most of human evolution.
  • However, humans have achieve ecological dominance
    so that weve not had to fear predation by other
    species for the past 15-20,000 years. Even
    before then, predation by other species was
    minimized at a relatively small group size
    compared to the size of human clans, tribes and
    nations.
  • 3. So why do we live in such large groups?!

17
If humans are not the prey of other species, do
they still suffer predation?
  • Yes, of course! We are our own prey! Predation
    by other human groups is likely to have been a
    big adaptive problem for our species!!
  • (N.B. Our overlooking this suggest how the
    ecological dominence of modern humans biases our
    thinking about the ancestral environment?)

18
  • For many thousands of years the most
    significant predator on group living humans has
    been other group living humans. To explain how
    this could cause humans live in very large
    groups, Alexander proposed the balance of power
    model

19
The Balance of Power Model
  • i. In multi-group environments, the members
    felt vulnerability is inversely related to the
    relative size of their group.
  • Felt vulnerability motivates smaller groups to
    form coalitions whose size counter-balances or
    excedes that of the previously largest group.
  • As a result, felt vulnerability decreases among
    members of the newly formed coalition (and
    increases among members of the previously largest
    group).
  • This in turn motivates the latter also to seek
    coalition partners which, if successful, motives
    the former to seek further coalition partners
    etc. Thus, group size spirals upward to some
    limit where there is a balance of power that
    minimizes feelings of vulnerability and
    additional coalitions are too costly or
    unavailable.

20
Living inKin Groups is Easier to Explain Than
Living in Non-Kin Groups
  • The protection function of groups implies
    altruism Group members willingly incur large
    costs to benefit others (e.g., some will risk
    death to protect fellow members from an animal
    predator or a raiding group).
  • Until the second half of the last century the
    fact of altruism, was a puzzle. How could such
    tendencies evolve if they cause harm to the actor
    and should be selected against? In 1964 Hamilton
    showed how in his analysis of inclusive fitness
    (kin selection).

21
A Heuristic for Thinking about Hamiltons Theory
  • Imagine you are a gene that contributes to the
    trait of intelligence. You know that
  • An individual is your vehicle carries you
    through life.
  • Intelligence contributes to fitness (increases
    RS).
  • The probability that copies of you exist in
    relatives of your vehicle increases with their
    degree of relatedness to your vehicle.
  • Then answer the following question
  • What what strategy would you want your vehicle
    to follow if your goal is insure that copies of
    you continue to exist in future generations?

22
Hamiltons Inequality Solves Two Related
Problems Why Living in Kin Groups is Adaptive
and How Altrusim Can be Positively Selected
23
(No Transcript)
24
(No Transcript)
25
(No Transcript)
26
(No Transcript)
27
(No Transcript)
28
(No Transcript)
29
Risky Decisions Involving a Large Non-Kin Group,
a Small Non-Kin Group, or My Family
  • The next study indicates that when making a risky
    decision for a group, the size of the group and
    our ties to its members can cause us to behave
    seemily irrationally, i.e., compute costs and
    benefits in sub-optimal fashion.
  • In what sense are such behaviors irrational?
  • According to behavioral decision theory or
    inclusive fitness theory or both?
  • Does this consider that adaptations are designed
    for recurrent problems, not rare events.

30
Framing of Choices in the Tversky and Kahneman
(1981) Decision Task
  • The decision task
  • Imagine that Lodz is preparing for the outbreak
    of an unusual disease which is expected to kill
    600 people.
  • Two alternative programs to combat the disease
    have been proposed.
  • Assume that the exact scientific estimates of the
    consequences of the programs are as follows

31
Positive framing of the Decision Task
  • The Certain outcome. If program A is adopted 200
    people will be saved.
  • The Uncertain outcome. If program B is adopted,
    there is a one-third probability that 600 people
    will be save and a two-third probability that no
    people will be saved.

32
Negative framing of the Decision Task
  • Certain outcome. If program C is adopted, 400
    people will die.
  • Uncertain outcome. If program D is adopted,
    there is a one-third probability that nobody will
    die and a two-third probability that 600 people
    will die.

33
Tversky and Kahnemans results
  • Under positive framing of the decision people are
    risk averse
  • 72 of their respondents chose the certain
    outcome.
  • 28 of them chose the uncertain or probabilistic
    outcome.

34
Tversky and Kahnemans results
  • Under negative framing people are risk prone
  • 22 chose the certain outcome.
  • 78 chose the probabilistic or uncertain outcome.

35
Peculiar Parameters of theTversky-Kahneman
Decision Task (Wang, 1996 2002)
  • The Group is Large and Its Members Have No Ties
    to the Respondent.
  • What Do You Think Would Happen If the Group is
    Small and the Decision Makers Ties to the Group
    Are Strong?

36
Risk Proneness Decreases with Group Size and
Kinship
37
Risk Aversion is Sensitive to Survival Rates for
Non-Kin Groups But Not for Kin Groups (Choices
are Positively Framed)
38
Decisions about Kin Groups Violate Rational
Choice Preferences Under Positive Framing for
Probabilistic Outcomes When Its Expected Value is
Less than that of the Certain Outcome
Choice Percentage
Non-kin
Kin
Proportion of Group Saved for Certain
(Note In all conditions the probalistic outcome
is 1/3rd chance of saving all group members)
39
Members of Kin Groups Are Nice to Each Other
But Not Under All Conditions
  • Parental investment hypothesis (derived from
    inclusive fitness theory) argues parents should
    incur a cost to benefit a child when it
    contributes to parents inclusive fitness more
    than doing something else with their resources.
    If so, what should be predicted (think of the
    earlier heuristic)
  • 1. When parents decide on investing in a male
    versus a female offspring?
  • 2. When parents are rich versus when they are
    poor?
  • 3. When they are step-parents?

40
Recall Hamiltons Inequality
  • Note that it says under certain conditions
    altruism toward kin may actually decrease
    inclusive fitness. This happens when
  • r 0 and/or C gt r B
  • As relatedness (r) between donor and recipient
    decreases and the cost of altruism (C) increases
    the donor should act in an increasingly
    unaltruistic manner. The next slides summarizes
    research (Wilson Daly, 1998) comparing the
    likelihood of child abuse and child homocide,
    decidedly unaltruistic acts, in families with two
    biological parents and families with one
    stepparent (typically the father). It
    emphatically supports Hamiltons prediction.

41
(No Transcript)
42
(No Transcript)
43
(No Transcript)
44
However a Violent Father or Brother Did Have
Benefits
  • When a relative was murdered, Vikings had the
    choice between a revenge murder or accepting
    blood money. Berserkers were individuals with a
    reputation of being extremely fierce and
    dangerous. If a murderer was a berserker (or his
    father or brother), the aggrieved relatives of
    the victim were significantly more likely to
    accept blood money, but to prefer a revenge
    killing if the murderer was not a berserker or a
    close relative.
  • In the next slide the plotted variable is the
    ratio of observed murders relative to the number
    expected on the basis of the proportion of
    berserkers or non-berserkers in the population.
    Source 34 murders recorded in Njal's Saga.

45
(No Transcript)
46
Viking berserkers suffered significantly higher
rates of mortality at the hands of their own
community but their behavior benefitted male
members of their families. Therefore,
Berserkers were altruists, yes? (Families of the
three berserkers in the Icelandic Njals Saga
suffered significantly less mortality than the 7
families that did not contain a recognized
berserker.)
120 100 80 60 40 20 01
47
Something to Think About
  • From the 8th through the 10th century, the
    Vikings were the fiercest and most feared group
    in Europe, raiding and plundering settlements on
    the northern and western coasts of the continent
    as well as the interior of eastern Europe.
  • A dozen centuries later their descendents are the
    most peaceful and least feared group in Europe.

48
  • In light of Hamiltons theory, how could
    cooperation among non-kin evolve?

49
Non-kin Altruism, Cooperation and Equity Some
Questions for Later
  • 1. Have the benefits of cooperation
    sufficiently outweighed its costs (transaction
    costs and opportunity costs) to create selection
    pressures on human psychology?
  • 2. Can large cooperative networks (e.g.,
    markets, trading networks) function without
    cognitive adaptations that allow participants to
    calculate the risks of a transaction?

50
  • 3. Are there indirect benefits of non-kin
    altruism (e.g., giving money to charity to poor
    strangers)?
  • 4. Are costly acts with no return benefit
    (e.g., altruistic punishment in a one-shot
    prisoners dilemma game) more a matter of
    satisfying a need for equity or fairness than
    true altruism? Or a need for vegence? If so,
    how would such motives be positively selected?

51
Skinnerians and others of their ilk say
Altruism need not assume the operation of
cognitive adaptations like cheater-detection,
empathy or Theory of Mind
  • A radical behaviorist demonstrates that helping a
    stranger develops and is maintained because it
    the act of helping is reinforced by its
    consequences.
  • Hence assumptions about cognitve adaptations are
    theoretically unnecessary, a violation of
    scientific parsimony.

52
  • In the following experiment subjects are free to
    press a button as quickly as they want to record
    the end of a trial. In two conditions this also
    turns off a noxious noise piped into a strangers
    ears i on every trial (continuous
    reinforcment), ii on some randomly selected
    trials (partial reinforcement), or iii on none
    of the trials (control), where the noise ends
    automatically after a fixed interval. The desire
    or effort to help is indicated by how quickly the
    subject presses the button.
  • N.B. The stranger is a confederate of the
    experimenter and there is no actual noise being
    piped into his ears.

53
(No Transcript)
54
A Question to Ponder
  • If humans do persist in helping strangers and if
    they do so because the act is intrinsically
    reinforcing, where does that leave theories that
    assumes complex computations of costs and
    benefits plus discounting (e.g., for age, health,
    relatedness, etc.) are necessary for the
    evolution of such behavior?

55
THE STRUGGLE BETWEEN BEHAVIORISTS AND
COGNITIONISTS CONTINUES IS COOPERATION MINDLESS
OR DO YOU NEED COGNITIVE ADAPTATIONS?
  • Sidowski Cooperation in essentially
    coordinating interpersonal behavior and can be
    achieved when individuals are totally unaware
    they are interacting with another person. Just
    assume the Law of Effect or Win-Stay,
    Lose-Change and forget about complex
    computations.
  • Kelly Not true. You need to think, to take the
    others perspective and think about what they are
    thinking to achieve cooperation. Let me show
    you..

56
The Sidowski-Kelley Coordination Game
57
The results of applying the Win-Stay-Lose-Change
rule when both players, P and O, respond
simultaneously. Note that there are only three
combination of button-press choices possible on
the first trial and from then on the
Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule determines each
players outcomes
58
The Three Starting Combinations
  • a. P chooses the right button and O the left.
    As a result both receive positive outcomes.
  • b. Both P and O choose the left button. As a
    result P receives a positive outcome and O a
    negative outcome. (N.B. The case in which both
    choose the right button is isomorphic with this
    one.)
  • c. P chooses the left button and O the right.
    As a result both receive negative outcomes.

59
Win-Stay, Lose-Change Wins An Ambiguous Triumph
for Radical Behavior Theory
60
  • According the Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule,
    cooperation (mutual reward) is inevitable under
    conditions of simultaneous responding which turns
    out to be the case whether or not P believes O is
    another person or a computer.
  • But see what happens when one simple parameter is
    changed, i.e., P and O respond in alternation
    rather than simultaneously. Suppose O responds
    first and P second. The three starting trials
    are as follows (continuing to apply the
    Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule as before)

61
Win-Stay Doesnt Win An Unambiguous Triumph for
Social Cognition
62
  • Unless they start out cooperating (a mutually
    rewarding exchange), they should never achieve
    cooperation according to the Win-Stay-Lose-Change
    rule.
  • But they do achieve cooperation if P knows O is
    another person (not, say, a computer). How is
    this possible? Well, not by using Skinnerian
    reinforcement theory which is inadequate to
    explain this effect. We have to go elsewhere
    for an explanation. Where? What assumption do
    we need to make beyond those of reinforcement
    theory to explain how cooperation is possible in
    a mutual-fate-control sitution when we know our
    outcome depends on another person, a stranger,
    and his or her outcome on us?

63
  • New Assumptions TOM, Foresight and Planning
    Cooperative Thinking
  • To achieve cooperation under these conditions we
    foresee having to adjust our strategies and
    actions with those of others so as to reconcile
    potential conflicts of interests with maximum
    benefit or least cost. To do so we represent in
    our mind, as best we can,what others intend to do
    (their plan or strategy), and what they think we
    intend to do (our plan or strategy).
  • Why?
  • In order to decide whether others are
    trustworthy.
  • In order to anticipate and, thus, coordinate each
    othersactions, thereby achieving a mutually
    beneficial or least costly relationship (e.g.,
    reciprocity or division of labor).

64
  • The most common experimental paradigms for
    observing cooperative thinking is the two-person
    prisoners dilemma game (PDG) and the n-person
    prisoners dilemma game (SDG).

65
The Classic PDG
66
The Social Dilemma Game (SDG)
  • The SDG is an n-person (n gt 2) PDG. Say, as the
    next Table assumes at least 5 out of a group of 7
    members have to contribute their endowment a
    sum of 5 given them at the beginning of the
    experiment to fund a public good. The latter
    means that all members will benefit by receiving
    10 whether or not they incurred the cost of the
    public good, i.e., whether they were a
    contributor or a non-contributor. So like all
    public goods, all members, contributor and
    non-contributors benefit if the group meets the
    cost criterion. Do you see why this creates a
    conflict of interest similar to that in the PDG?

67
  • As in the PDG the largest benefit or payoff goes
    to defectors (i.e., non-contributors) if there
    are enough cooperators (i.e., contributors) to
    provide the public good.
  • The next largest goes to the cooperators if
    enough others cooperate to provide the public
    good.
  • The next largest goes to defectors if there are
    not enough cooperators to provide the public
    good.
  • And least benefit, the suckers payoff goes to
    cooperators when there are too few to provid the
    public good.

68
  • Next we lay out the conditions that define the
    standard SDG
  • It is a non-iterated (one-shot) game.
  • Members are strangers.
  • Their decisions are completely anonymous.
  • There is no contact or discussion prior to,
    during or after the decisions. They arrive and
    leave the experiment never have seen any member
    of their group.

69
  • Non-standard versions devised to compare with the
    standard SDG
  • Money-back is a norm imposed on the group that
    guarantees cooperators will get their money back
    if there are two few of them to provide the
    public good, ergo, no one gets a suckers payoff
    and looses his endowment.
  • No free-riders is a norm imposed on the group
    that guarantees defectors will not benefit more
    than cooperators if the public good is provided,
    ergo, there is no temptation to defect.

70
The standard SDG and variations in Caporeal,
Dawes, Orbell and van de Kragt (1989)
Cooperation requires a minimum number of members
to contribute.
71
  • Some SDG studies also vary
  • Whether or not individuals have a brief
    discussion prior to deciding anonymously.
  • Whether or not the experimenter designated who
    was to contribute (but they could still defect
    because their decision is anonymous).
  • Whether or not everybody had to contribute
    (called super simple because members did not
    have to decide about cooperating but again anyone
    could still defect since their decision is
    anonymous).

72
Rates of Public Goods Provision
73
Rates of Contribution when External Authority
Designates the Anonymous Contributors
74
Intergroup Cooperation Is Distrust of the Other
the Default for Outgroups (Even Minimal
Outgroups)?
75
Reciprocity Knowing and Providing What is Due
Another Uncompelled Equity and Fairness
  • 1. Will a person abide by a contract when it
    is costly to do so and the person cannot be
    punished for defecting?
  • 2. Will a person punish defectors when it is
    costly to do so and it cannot force them to
    cooperate?
  • 3. Will a person expect to receive punishment
    as a result of defecting when punishment is
    costly to adminsiter and it cannot benefit the
    punisher (by compelling cooperation)?
  • If you say yes to any or all of these
    propositions what does it imply about equity and
    fairness as an adaptation?

76
Employees Contracted and Delivered Effort in
One-Shot (non-repeated) Employer-Employee
Gain (see Gintis, et al., 2003)
Employees Average Effort
Payoff Offer to Employee by Employer
77
The Mystery of Altruistic Punishment
  • Cooperation can be maintain by punishing
    free-riders.
  • Humans seem designed to punish non-cooperators in
    that they do so even when it is costly and there
    is no direct return benefit (e.g., in a one-shot
    exchange).
  • If punishment of free-riding is costly and cannot
    elicit return benefits from the free-rider, how
    can it be postively selected and become an
    adaptation? iveEven when it is costly to them and
    they do not directly benefit as a result (e.g.,
    in a one-shot game)?

78
Contributions in a repeated public goods game
with the same partner or a new partner (stranger)
under conditions of punishment and non-punishment
(see Gintis, et al., 2003)
Punishment option Removed
Punishment Permitted
Average Contribution
Games
79
  • Milgrams study of obediance is the best known
    study with data about what people expect someone
    to do when punishing another person. At first
    glance, the findings seem to argue against
    assuming the tendency to punish free-riders is an
    adaptation.
  • But does it? Is the person being punished
    free-riding? If not, does the finding imply
    anything about tendencies to punish in the
    absence of free-riding? Let look at Milgrims
    data.

80
Punishing Members Who Refuse to Punish Deviants
May Be Unnecessary to Produce Conformity
Predictions that People (including Self) Will
Refuse to Punish Deviant Learner Are Wrong.
81
(No Transcript)
82
Cooperation and the Division of Labor
  • The division of labor is probably the most common
    form of cooperation in everyday life.
  • It is occurs when (i) members know, prefer to or
    can do different things and (ii) coordinate their
    respective knowledge or performances to their
    mutual benefit.
  • The division of labor can be not only formal,
    explicit and hierarchical (e.g., military units,
    sports teams, surgical teams, business teams,
    etc.) but also informal, implicit and egalitarian
    (e.g., families, friends, co-workers and lovers).

83
Cooperation Depends on Trust
  • Contrary to Axelrod, simulation studies
    demonstrate that his best game strategy,
    TIT-FOR-TAT, really isnt. Actually, it counts
    for little in respect to inclusive fitness
    compared to the partner-selection strategy, i.e.,
    being able to distinguish between trustworthy and
    untrustworthy partners ahead of time.
  • If so, then humans, being so eminently
    cooperative and cooperation being so vulneralbe
    to cheating, must be designed to detect potential
    cheaters somehow. You agree, of course? Well
    okay, what do we know about such mechanism?

84
The DOG Partner Selection Algorithm
  • The secret to DOGs success
  • 1 Unlike the other partner selection
    strategies, when it assesses the trustworthiness
    of a potential partner DOG ignores transaction
    costs it doesnt care whether a player
    cooperated or defected in prior transactions.
  • ii Instead it focuses only on opportunity
    costs it tries to select the player offering the
    highest potential return and never selects a
    player one offering a negative return regardless
    of whether the player previously defected or
    cooperated.

85
  • How does DOG work?
  • 1. On the first trial DOG assigns a random
    preference rank to all other players.
  • 2. From the second trial on, DOG assigns a
    preference rank to all the other players
    according to the following X-value rule
  • a. For any player DOG has ever played in the
    past, the X-value is the score DOG earned in the
    most recent transaction with that player (X can
    vary from some positive value to some negative
    value, i.e., it can reflect a large, moderate or
    small positive or negative return from the
    transaction).
  • b. In the case of a stranger, a player with
    whom DOG has never played, X is the average of
    the positive X-values of the players with whom
    DOG has played in the past.
  • 3. On each trial DOG first selects the player
    with the largest X-value.
  • 4. If that player doesnt select DOG as a
    partner within three matching rounds, DOG selects
    the player with the second largest X-value.
  • 5. This process continues until all the players
    with positive X-values are exhausted at which
    point DOG returns to the player with largest
    X-value that is still available and repeats the
    whole process, ad infinitum.

86
Evidence for mechanism to assess the likelihood
of defecting, cheating, free-riding and
untrustworthiness
87
(No Transcript)
88
Abstract Rule Example
  • Rule If you are in category X you have to be
    taller than 6.0 feet. Is the rule being
    violated?
  • Card P Someone who is in category X.
  • Card not-P Someone who is in category Y.
  • Card Q Someone who is 6.5 feet.
  • Card not-Q Someone who is 5.5 feet.

89
Social Norm Example
  • Norm If you are drinking alcohol you have to be
    21 or older. Is it being violated?
  • Card P Someone is drinking a beer.
  • Card not-P Someone is drinking a coke.
  • Card Q Someone is 23 years old.
  • Card not-Q Someone is 17 years old.

90
What Makes Us More Trustworthy?
  • H.L. Menken (Its) the little voice inside
    of you that says someone is watching. Which
    implies concern about
  • 1. Being monitored.
  • 2. Reputation.
  • 3. Opportunity costs (i.e., other members
    reject you as a partner in transactions involving
    trust).
  • 4. Other kinds of punishment (e.g., make
    him an offer he cant refuse ).

91
Concern about being monitored can implicit and
automatic in transactions involving trust
Computer Monitor (Haley Fessler, 2005)
92
Probability of Allocation Funds to an Agent to
Invest in the Trust Game
Effects of Eyes and Crowd-Noise on Allocation
N 24
N 24
N 29
N 22
N 25
(Haley Fessler, 2005)
93
Cues to Trust and Distrust
  • Aside from Cosmides cheater-detection mechanism
    she demonstrated using the Wason Selection task,
    are there other situational or internal cues
    besides reputation, payoff structure (e.g.,
    temptations to defect in PDG) and transparency of
    return (e.g., rice versus rubber markets) that
    are used to compute or infer trustworthiness?
  • 1. Self-resemblance Facial self-morphing
    (conscious and unconscious effects).
  • 2. Facial prototypes Defector recognition
    (specific features, e.g., eye shape?).
  • 3. How you feel (mood) Oxytocin inhalation.
  • 4. Brain activity Anticipation of returns.

94
Whom Do You Trust? Self Resemblance Studies
Using Facial Morphs
95
Plt.08
Plt.01
Plt.001
NS
Plt.01
Experimental Control
Experiment 1
Experiment 2
Experiment 3
Experiment 4
96
Effects of Qxytocin on Investor Transfers with
Human (Trust) and Programmed (Risk)
Trustee (Kosfeld, Heinrichs, Zak, Fischbacher,
Fehr, 2005)
97
Neural Correlates of Reputation Building in
Trustee Brain (King-Casas, Tomlin, Anew, Camerer,
Quartz, Montague, 2005)
98
Human Adaptations for Cheater Detection
Information Processing and Computation Under
Focused and Unfocused Distrust
  • In many situations we know who may be tempted to
    deceive us. Sometimes, however, we do not.
  • Focused distrust refers to occasions when we
    suspect deception and know the source.
  • Unfocused distrust refers to occasions when we
    suspect deception without being aware of its
    source something just doesnt seem right.
  • Have we evolved to process information under
    these two conditions differently compared to when
    we trust others?

99
Cheater-detection makes us think more
  • If we elaborate on and analyze a lot what
    suspected cheaters say, then we should confuse
    what their actual statements with inferences we
    made while encoding them.
  • Examples of types of inferences
  • Direct inference Her boss says Mary works
    quickly and doesnt make mistakes and we infer
    Mary is an efficient worker.
  • Compound inference Her boss says Mary works
    quickly etc., and we give a bonus to our most
    efficient workers. We infer Mary won a bonus.

100
(No Transcript)
101
(No Transcript)
102
Favorable
Neutral
Favorable ? Unfavorable
Unfavorable ? Favorable
Unfavorable
103
(No Transcript)
104
Suspicion Can Influence Judgment Unconsciously
  • In recent experiments a few seconds before they
    make a judgment, individuals are subliminally
    primed with a word (e.g., an adjective or noun)
    presented imbedded in a supraliminal honest or
    dishonest face.
  • The word prime as well as the face is irrelevant
    to the judgments they are about to make (e.g., Is
    a second word, presented above threshold, an
    adjective or a noun?).

105
  • The model tested in these experiments assumes
    they will elaborate congruent associates to the
    subliminal word prime in the honest-face context
    and incongruent associates to the subliminal word
    prime in the dishonest-face context.
  • If so, the model predicts that
  • when the prime and the to-be judged word are
    both nouns or both adjectives, then in the
    honest-face context individuals will elaborate
    congruent associates to the prime (e.g., the
    concept of noun or specific nouns when both the
    prime and the supraliminal word are nouns) and
    categorization of the to-be-judged word is
    facilitated (e.g., faster) whereas in the
    dishonest-face context they elaborates
    incongruent associates (e.g., the concept of
    adjective or specific adjectives when both words
    are nouns) and categorization is disrupted (e.g.,
    slower).
  • by the same logic, when the to-be-judged word is
    incongruent with the prime (e.g., one is a noun,
    the other an adjective), judgments will be
    disrupted (e.g., slower) in the honest-face
    context and facilitated in the dishonest-face
    context.

106
(No Transcript)
107
(No Transcript)
108
(No Transcript)
109
(No Transcript)
110
(No Transcript)
111
Being able to efficiently process information
about our relations with others (e.g., Is he or
she a friend or foe? Is his or her status higher
or lower than mine?) is useful. Is there
evidence that humans are designed to make and
store such computations?
112
Adaptations Mechanisms for Coding Social
Relations
  • If humans are designed to live in groups, then
    they are also likely to be designed to code
    (i.e., recognize, interpret, remember and
    elaborate upon) information that reduces the
    costs of group living and increase its benefits.
  • Among the most adaptive pieces of information
    concern relations among group members
  • Who in the group have common interests, are
    friends, who have conflicting interests, are
    enemies?
  • Who is has high status (i.e., is powerful, rich,
    skillful, etc.), who has low status (i.e., is
    weak, poor, inept, etc.)?

113
(No Transcript)
114
(No Transcript)
115
(No Transcript)
116
(No Transcript)
117
(No Transcript)
118
A Procedure for Assessing Cognitive
Categorization of Individuals Are They Perceived
as Belonging Together, Forming a Coalition or
Unit?
119
Suppose You Wanted to Know If Observers Grouped
People Based on Common Interest or Opinion.
  • Tell observers about some characteristic of the
    people (e.g., sex, age, race, clothes, and what
    they said that indicated whether they were pro
    or con regarding an issue).
  • Next ask observers to recall if an individual
    made a particular statement (e.g., whether he or
    she said X).
  • Count how often the individual is confused with
    another (e.g., observers say he or she made the
    statement when it was actually made by another).

120
  • What was the reason for these confusions? Did
    they occur most often if the two individuals were
    the same sex, the same age, the same race, wore
    the same t-shirt or had the same opinion (both
    were either pro or con)?
  • Intra-category confusion are most frequent.
    Therefore, if confusion occurred most often
    between those with the same opinion (both were
    pro or both con), then its evidence that
    observers were categorizing or cognitively
    grouping the individuals based on common opinions
    or common interests. Kurzban calls this
    coalitional thinking. In Heider, the
    grouping would reflect a positive unit
    relationship and, perhaps implicitly, a
    positive sentiment relationship.

121
(No Transcript)
122
(No Transcript)
123
Social Dominance Orientation Following Ethnic
Prime (Questions on Ashkenazi-Sephardi Relations)
or National Prime (Questions on
Israeli-Palestinian Relations)
124
(No Transcript)
125
Consensus and Conformity
  • Intentional cooperation typically is a form of
    collective action (e.g., several friends decide
    to form a study group, a community decides to
    subsidize medical care for the poor a
    hunter-gatherer tribe decide to migrate a
    country decides to go to war) based on consensus.
  • An effective consensus must prevent cheating and
    free-riding.
  • This implies social psychological mechanisms to
    minimize distrust and insure conformity.
  • i. Informational influence (e.g., Sherif)
  • social comparison
  • persuasive argumentation
  • ii. Normative influence (e.g., Asch)
  • extrinsic reward or punishment

126
But first, the mystery of compliance and human
nature
  • What conclusion do you draw about human nature
    from the amazing (okay, amazing only to the
    naïve) relationship between (i) predicted and
    actual compliance and (ii) proximity of victim
    to punisher and the amount of pain the latter
    is willing to inflict on the former?
  • Is there other evidence (e.g., studies of
    soldiers ordered to shoot someone)?
  • Implications for normative influence and
    conformity and second order punishment?

127
(No Transcript)
128
(No Transcript)
129
(No Transcript)
130
(No Transcript)
131
(No Transcript)
132
The Benefits and Cost of Conformity
  • You dont have to learn what to believe or how to
    do something. Just imitate others actions and
    conform to their beliefs.
  • Social comparison as an adaptive mechanism for
    imitation and conformity.
  • But imitation and conformity may have opportunity
    costs, i.e., you will not discover that there are
    better ways of doing something or that there are
    more valid views of the world.
  • Hence, humans may be designed to discount the
    validity of others actions or beliefs to the
    extent that these actions and beliefs are
    themselves products of conformity (not
    independently arrived at) and are not objectively
    demonstrable.
  • Is this why conformity in Asch-like normative
    influence settings doesnt increase when
    unanimous majority becomes relatively large?

133
Why Normative Influence Peaks at a Very Small
Unanimous Majority
  • 1. Discounting mechanisms
  • i. Majority has shared interests different
    from that of deviant.
  • ii. Non-independence of majority members.
  • 2. Futile search for independent evidence or
    objective demonstration of the majority choice.
  • Search is typically done under time stress and at
    the cost of cognitive inconsistency (i.e., the
    majority seems incorrect) relative to the cost of
    social rejection.

134
Conformity to a Unanimous Blame-the-Mother-Not-th
e-Manufacturer Majority in a One Six Member
Group, Two Three Member Groups and Three Two
Member Groups
10K 9K 8K 7K 6K 5K 4K
Degree of Blame
135
Conformity to a Unanimous Blame-the-Mother-Not-th
e-Manufacturer Majority in Groups and in
Non-Groups (Aggregates of Individuals) of
Identical Sizes
Degree of Blame
136
(No Transcript)
137
(No Transcript)
138
  • According to Mueller and Mazur (1997), we
    automatically judge someons status or dominence
    from his or her face (Mueller and Mazur, 1997).
  • The faces used by Mueller and Mazur are from a
    yearbook published by West Point, the U.S.
    Military Academy, that trains career army
    officers. Some examples (Can you detect
    differences in facial dominance?)

139
(No Transcript)
140
  • See slides based on WHO data for male-female
    differences in mortality as a function of status
    competition.

141
Mating
  • What does sexual selection theory predict about
    male-female difference in
  • 1. Preferred number of partners?
  • 2. Probability of consenting to intercourse?
  • 3. Preferred age difference in mate?
  • 4. Importance of mates provisioning prospects?
  • 5. Importance of mates attractiveness?

142
(No Transcript)
143
(No Transcript)
144
(No Transcript)
145
(No Transcript)
146
(No Transcript)
147
Male-Female Differences in Antecedents and
Consequences of Homicide Demographic Evidence
  • How (if at all) might theories of sex differences
    in mating strategies, especially their
    implications regarding competition between and
    within the sexes, explain the differences in the
    following data sets?

148
Risky Competition Age- and sex-specific homicide
rates in Canada, 1974-1983.
Female victims
Homicides per million persons per annum
Age (years)
Female offenders
Age (years)
149
(No Transcript)
150
Age- and Sex-specific Rates of Homicide in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
Male victims
Homicides per million persons per annum
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
Male offenders
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
151
Age- and Sex-specific Rates of Homicide in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
Female victims
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Homicides per million persons per annum
Age (years)
Female offenders
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
152
(No Transcript)
153
Unemployment Rates Among Male Homicide Offenders,
Male victims, and the Male Population-at-Large in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
154
Proportions Unmarried Among Male Homicide
Offenders, Male victims, and the Male
Population-at-Large in Detroit, 1972. (From
Wilson Daly, 1985)
155
Spousal Homicde Rates as a Function of the Age
Difference Between Wife and Husband. Canada,
1974-1983.
Wife older
Wife younger
156
Motive Categories and the Number of Cases
(Victims) Within Each, for 588 Criminal Homicides
in the City of Philadelphia, 1948-1952. (From
Wolfgang, 1958)
157
Two hundred Twelve Closed Social Conflict
homicides in Detroit, 1972, in Which Victim and
Offender Were Unrelated (Friends, Acquaintances
or Strangers), Classified by Conflict Typology
and by the Sexes of the Principals. (From
Wilson and Daly, 1985)
158
Dispositions of Spousal Homicides in Various
Studies. (Data from Canada and Detroit are from
Daly Wilson, 1988 for Miami from Wilbanks,
1984 and for Houston from Lundsgaarde, 1977)
159
The Probability of Suicide After Homicide, in
Relation to the Sexes of Killer and Victim, and
Their Relationship, Canada, 1974-1983
160
Intergroup Relations
  • 1. Realistic Group Conflict Theory (Sherif)
    versus Social Categorization Theory (Tajfel)
    Are they incompatible?
  • 2. The minimal intergroup situation Is
    advantaging the ingroup (or disadvantaging
    outgroups) the default reaction to social
    categorization? Is strategy likely to have been
    adaptive (positively selected for) in the
    ancestral environment
  • 3. What about N-group (not merely one in-group
    and one outgroup) environments and coalitions as
    in the balance-of-power model?
  • 4. Group/category membership, the hierarchy of
    groups/categories, and self-evaluation Are
    there dimensions other than prestige or power for
    ordering groups?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)