TOPIC4: INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 50
About This Presentation
Title:

TOPIC4: INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE

Description:

there is no demand for insurance from an individual who is a gambler or ... to leave the house/car door unlocked after purchasing insurance against burglary? ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:169
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 51
Provided by: city104
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: TOPIC4: INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE


1
TOPIC4 INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE
  • Saving for tomorrow is a fact of life.
  • Equally, we often spend more than what we
    currently earn or have by borrowing.

2
  • We shall consider a two-period model of consumer
    choice.
  • The consumer receives a given amount of money in
    period 0 (M0), and in period 1 (M1). The numbers
    M0 and M1 thus define the consumers budget.
  • The consumer derives utility from todays
    consumption(C0) and tomorrows consumption C1
    according to some utility function U(C0,C1)
    which generates an indifference map as shown in
    below.
  •  

3
Relate this diagram to the explanation in the
next slide
C1
o
C0
4
An individual who borrows has a stronger
preference for C0 (steeper indifference curves).
  • The slope of the indifference curve is the
  • MRS between C0 and C1.

The MRS is also called the discount factor.
5
  • People with stronger preference for C0 have a
    smaller discount factor.
  • They discount future happiness more.
  • The discount factor is unique to an individual
    consumer, just like his/her indifference curves.

6
  • The budget constraint of the consumer must
    recognise the fact that the consumer is free to
    borrow and/or lend at the market interest rate r.
  • For a given value of r, the budget constraint is
    drawn below
  • (We assume for simplicity that the unit price of
    both C0 and C1 is 1)

7
OB ? M0(1r) M1
The negative sign represents the trade-off the
magnitude (1r) is the relative price of C0 in
terms of C1.
c1
B
The slope of the budget line (-OB/OA) -(1r) .
M1
c0
O
A
M0
OA ? M0 M1/(1r)
8
Consumer choice The individual is a saver
c1
b
C1
M1
c0
O
A
M0
C0
9
c1
A drop in the rate of interest Shifts AB down and
to the right
b
M1
c0
O
A
M0
10
A fall in the rate of interest is a gain for the
borrower but a loss to the lender
B
M0 A A C0
11
An increase in the interest rate reduces the
welfare of the borrower
c1
b
b
M1
1
2
c0
O
A A
M0
12
An increase in the interest rate increases the
welfare of the lender
c1
b
2
b
In this case, as the interest rate goes up, C0
falls
1
M1
c0
O
A A
M0
The law of demand holds
13
In this case, as the interest rate goes up, so
does C0.
c1
b
b
The law of demand does not hold
2
1
M1
c0
O
A A
M0
14
Inter-temporal Choice with Production
  • The analysis above assumes that the individual
    can reallocate consumption across time by
    borrowing/lending in a perfect capital market.

15
  • However, instead of having just the freedom to
    lend current resources, it may be more realistic
    to include the possibility of using the current
    resources to produce some goods that are
    consumable in the future, or INVESTMENT.
  • We shall therefore broaden our analysis by
    incorporating a production opportunity that
    allows current saving to be invested, leading to
    a greater level of output in the future.

16
  • To start with a simple model,
  • suppose that the individual has no access to a
    capital market. ,
  • that is, she is unable to borrow/lend.
  • Also, for simplicity, we assume that the
    individual is endowed with productive resources
    only for today (she does not receive any
    resources tomorrow).

17
C1
Individual has no access to an organized capital
market
Individual consumes OX units of C0.
B
Saves and invests AX units
Y
1
O X A
C0
Produces/consumes OY units of C1.
18
C1
Saving CI
Individual has access to an organized capital
market
B
2
Investment IA
1
1
O C I A
C0
19
Individual has access to an organized capital
market
C1
Saving -IC
1
B
2
1
Investment IA
O I A C
C0
20
TOPIC5 CONSUMER CHOICE UNDER RISK  
  • We have so far analysed consumer behaviour under
    certainty.
  • The typical consumer has been assumed to have
    perfect information on every single economic
    variable.
  • We shall now introduce the notion of RISK.

21
  • Consider the following choice problem.
  • Choice A Buy lottery ticket for 1 that wins 2
    with probability 0.5 or nothing with
    probability 0.5
  • Choice B Dont buy the ticket.

22
  • Consumer preferences may be one of the following
    three types
  • 1. Risk Lovers or Gamblers would prefer
    choice A to B.
  • 2. A Risk Neutral person would be indifferent
    between choice A and B. 
  • 3. A Risk Averse person would prefer choice B
    over A.

23
Utility
The utility from a gained is greater than the
disutility from a lost
O 1 2
Wealth
The utility function of a gambler
24
Utility
The utility from a gained is less than the
disutility from a lost
O 1 2
Wealth
The utility function of a risk-averse person
25
Utility
The utility from a gained is the same as the
disutility from a lost
O 1 2
Wealth
The utility function of a risk-neutral person
26
  • Consider this possibility. Individual says that  
  • U(A) lt U(B) U (1). That is,
  • although both A and B offers the same amount
    of money (1) on average, the individual would
    rather have B.
  • But what is U(A)?
  • It is certainly not as high as U(2).
  • Neither is it as low as U(0).

27
  • The value of U(A) is in between these extreme
    values.
  • To capture this idea, we introduce the notion of
    EXPECTED UTILITY.
  • .

28
  • We shall say that
  • Expected utility of lottery A, or EU (A) ? 0.5
    U(2) 0.5 U(0) .
  • Clearly, EU(A) is a weighted average of the two
    extreme values U(2) and U(0), using the
    probabilities as the weights.  
  • It then follows that
  •  U(2) gt EU(A) gt U(0)

29
  • For a gambler, EU(A) gt U(B).
  • Oppositely, for a risk-averse person EU(A) lt
    U(B)  
  • and for a risk neutral person
  • EU(A) U(B)

30
Risk Preference and the market for insurance
  • In this section we shall argue that
  • there is no demand for insurance from an
    individual who is a gambler or risk-neutral.
  • Risk-averse people will want to be insured
    against the risk,

31
  • but this alone does not guarantee the existence
    of a market as we shall shortly see.
  • We start with the case of a risk-averse person.
  • In order to generalise the argument above,
  • let the individual face a risky situation A
    described as follows
  •  
  •  
  •  

32
  • With a small probability ? the individual gets
    W0 unit s of money
  • and with probability (1-?) he gets W1 gt W0.
  • Let OB ? ?W0 (1-?)W1 .
  • OB is then the EXPECTED VALUE of the monetary
    gain.

33
Utility
U(OB)
EUA
O W0 C B W1
Wealth
34
OB EVA pW0 (1-p)W1
EUA pU(W0) (1-p)U(W1)
U(EVA) gt EUA for a risk-averse person
W1-B is the minimum insurance premium
C is the certainty equivalent of lottery A
W1-C is the maximum insurance premium
BC is the consumer surplus
35
  • It therefore seems that potentials of a market
    exist because the buyer could pay more than what
    the seller would charge.
  • But what about administrative costs?
  • If these exceed distance BC in the diagram
    above, there is no market!
  • As long as these costs are less than BC,
    potentials of a market exist.

36
  • The nature of admin costs is such that they do
    not change proportionately with the size of the
    policy or that of the premium.
  • On the other hand, notice that the consumer
    surplus BC is larger the greater the difference
    between W1 and W0.
  • Hence it follows that the consumer will not
    bother to buy insurance if the extent of the loss
    is small.

37
  • You should now be able to argue that a risk
    neutral person will not buy insurance if there
    are positive administrative costs.
  • What exactly are these administrative costs?
  • The insuring party typically pools the risk
    faced by several of its customers.

38
  • Suppose that 100 individuals each wants to
    purchase an insurance against unemployment.
  • Assume that they each earn 40000 p.a. and
    nothing if s/he loses job. Let the job loss
    probability for each be 0.1.
  • Here, the fair bet premium is 4000.

39
  • How much extra the seller charges depends how the
    job losses are correlated.
  • Essentially, the seller hopes to pay out a claim
    (by a customer who lost his job) from the money
    paid in by those who do not lose their jobs.
  • This can be ideally achieved if the event that
    one customer loses his job is negatively
    correlated with the one in which some other
    customer loses his.

40
  • The worst scenario for the insurer is when these
    events are perfectly and positively correlated.
  • For example, if all the workers work in the same
    factory, there can be no single insurer who can
    sell unemployment insurance to all of them.

41
  • This is why you cannot purchase insurance against
    earthquakes or floods.
  • A social risk is non-insurable.

42
An agent has the utility functionU W2 defined
over wealth (W)
Utility
Examine his attitude to risk
4
1
O 1 2
Wealth
The utility from a gained is greater than the
disutility from a lost
43
U(W1)
Utility
U W2
EUA
U(EVA)
U(W0)
O
W0 EVA W1
Wealth
Relate this diagram to the explanation in the
next slide
44
Let W0 100 and W1 200
Then U(W0) 10000 and U(W1) 40000
Suppose probability of getting W1 is 0.5
Then EVA 0.5200 0.5100 150
EUA 0.510000 0.540000 25000
25000 gt 22500
EU(A) gt U(EVA)
The agent is a gambler
45
40000
Utility
U W2
Maximum Premium 41.89
25000
22500
10000
O
100 150 200
Wealth ()
158.11
No market for insurance
Minimum Premium 50
46
Asymmetric Information and the Market for
Insurance
Moral Hazard Adverse Selection
  •  Are we more likely to leave the house/car door
    unlocked after purchasing insurance against
    burglary?
  • Does the probability of a risky event occurring
    increase as we insure ourselves against it?

47
  • Some economists answer in the affirmative.
  • If this is the case, then the profitability of
    the insurance seller may well be lower,
  • thus reducing the willingness of the seller to
    sell insurance and the probability of market
    existence.
  • This is the problem of moral hazard due to
    asymmetric information.

48
  • A second problem, and due to asymmetric
    information as well, is that of adverse
    selection.
  • Suppose that individual A is a low-risk case who
    wishes to purchase insurance.
  • Mr. A expects the premium to be low.  

49
  • Indeed, the seller would offer him a low premium
    rates if he knew that A was low-risk.
  • Unfortunately, he cannot distinguish Mr. A from
    Ms. B, a high-risk customer.
  • The presence of the latter kind of customers
    drives the cost of insurance higher than what the
    likes of Mr. A ought to pay.

50
  • On the other hand, such premiums are well below
    the rate that the high-risk customer ought to
    pay.
  • Result- low-risk customers such as Mr. A pull
    out of the market high-risk customers are the
    ones that remain.
  • The seller has managed to attract the worse type
    of customers to his business.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com