2' Intuitionism and the Structure of Morality - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 51
About This Presentation
Title:

2' Intuitionism and the Structure of Morality

Description:

What is buck-passing about value. Monism and pluralism about moral principles ... Thus, the 'buck' gets passed from value to base properties that give us reasons ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:342
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 52
Provided by: anttika
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: 2' Intuitionism and the Structure of Morality


1
2. Intuitionism and the Structure of Morality
2
Goals
  • Our aim today is to understand
  • The difference between attributive and
    predicative uses of good
  • What organic unities are
  • What is buck-passing about value
  • Monism and pluralism about moral principles
  • The relationship between prima facie duties, pro
    tanto reasons, and final duties
  • Arguments for and against the self-evidence of
    basic moral principles and judgments about
    intrinsic value

3
I What Is Good?
4
Two Uses of Good
  • As Peter Geach pointed out, we use the adjective
    good in two different ways
  • Predicative uses Knowledge is good
  • Attributive uses John is a good farmer
  • Geach argued that Moore and others made a big
    mistake in focusing on predicative uses, since
    they are secondary to attributive ones when we
    say that knowledge is good, we could always in
    principle fill in what we are taking it to be
    good for
  • Even when good and bad stands by itself as a
    predicate, and is thus grammatically predicative,
    some substantive has to be understood there is
    no such thing as being just good or bad, there is
    only being a good or bad so-and-so. (Good and
    Evil, 33)

5
An Argument for Attributiveness
  • A simple argument for this view
  • Real predicates can be combined with nouns
    without loss of truth (if x is red and x is a
    car, x is a red car), but good cannot
  • If x is good and x is a car, it does not follow
    that x is a good car x could be a good prop for
    a play, for example
  • Metaphysical explanation
  • Red always names the same quality that anything
    red has (red car, red book, red building), but
    good doesnt (a good car, a good book, and a
    good person need not share any quality)
  • The quality that good picks out in good car
    is not non-natural, so we can leave behind
    Moorean worries

6
Attributive Use of Good and the OQA
  • Importantly, there are many cases in which the
    OQA, even if otherwise sound, fails to apply to
    attributive uses of good
  • This knife fits nicely to the hand, cuts well,
    stays sharp for long, and looks expensive
    But is it good?
  • Her students admire her, learn a lot, acquire a
    passion for the subject, and go on to have great
    careers in it But is she a good teacher?
  • In these cases, good modifies a functional
    term the function in question sets a standard,
    and a good K just indicates an x that meets the
    standard in question
  • If this is the case, to know whether something x
    is a good K, all you need to know is what it
    takes to fulfil the function of K and whether x
    meets those standards no non-natural properties
    are ascribed

7
Against Attributivism
  • But on the face of it, not all things we call
    good have a function, as Hare points out in his
    response centrally, actions and human beings
    seem to lack one
  • Judith Jarvis Thompson agrees that all goodness
    is goodness in a way, but disagrees that kind
    membership is sufficient to supply the relevant
    standards
  • A good book may be such for entertainment,
    insight, showing off to your friends, and so on
    lots of things have no unique function, even if
    they have one
  • Philippa Foot has recently defended a
    neo-Aristotelian view according to which human
    beings and by derivation actions do have a
    function. The debate is still ongoing.

8
The Epistemological Problem for Non-Naturalism
  • By definition, non-natural properties are not
    within the causal realm, and (so) not observable
    nor amenable to scientific investigation
  • So, if goodness is a non-natural property, how
    can we discover when it is instantiated, i.e.
    which things have it? How can we know that one
    thing is better than another?
  • Do we need to postulate a special sense-like
    faculty of intuition?
  • If we have no other reason to do so, this would
    be entirely ad hoc

9
The Naturalistic Fallacy and Humes Law
  • We are, of course, able to perceive natural
    properties, so if we could deduce evaluative
    conclusions from natural premises, we would be
    off the hook
  • Helping Ms. Goldwater would maximize pleasure
  • Goodness maximizing pleasure (analytical truth)
  • So, helping Ms. Goldwater would be good
  • But embracing the OQA amounts to rejecting any
    identification of goodness with a natural
    property, and so premises like 2
  • Thus, the OQA prevents reaching conclusions about
    value from non-evaluative premises stating
    contingent natural facts and analytic truths
    truths about what is good are all synthetic
  • This is embracing the so-called Humes Law (no
    ought from is)

10
Moores Epistemological Intuitionism
  • Moore does think that there is a close
    relationship between a things natural properties
    and its value the value is consequential on the
    natural properties
  • This is what is now known as supervenience
  • Very roughly, if properties of type A supervene
    on properties of type B, then a) there can be no
    change in A-properties without change in
    B-properties and b) two things that have the same
    B-properties necessarily have the same
    A-properties
  • Still, in the absence of a naturalistic
    definition, there is no way for us to infer which
    natural properties form the base for value
    (ascriptions of intrinsic value are incapable of
    proof, as Moore says)
  • Instead, we know which things are good
    non-inferentially ascriptions of goodness are
    self-evident, once properly understood

11
Intrinsic and Final Value
  • It is clear that some things are good only in
    virtue of their relation to other things that
    is, they are good extrinsically
  • The clearest cases of extrinsic value are
    instrumentally good things ibuprofen pills are
    good for relieving headache
  • If anything is good, it seems that some things,
    must be good for their own sake they have what
    is known as final value
  • Moores term for final value is intrinsic value,
    but insofar as intrinsic value is consequential
    upon the intrinsic properties of something, the
    two kinds of value can diverge
  • The intrinsic properties of something are
    non-relational they do not require the
    existence of anything else
  • For example, Picassos Guernica and a
    qualitatively identical copy produced with the
    latest technology would share the same intrinsic
    properties, but would they be equally valuable?
  • Chisholm a rare stamp may be valuable in virtue
    of its rarity
  • Langton a wedding ring may be valuable for its
    own sake

12
The Principle of Organic Unities
  • Before we can answer the question of which things
    are intrinsically valuable which things have
    the non-natural property of goodness we must
    take note of the special relationship between
    valuable wholes and their parts
  • Moore believes in what he calls the principle of
    organic unities The intrinsic value of a whole
    is neither identical to nor proportional with the
    sum of the values of its parts. (PE, 184)
  • That is, if the value of part A is x and the
    value of part B y, the value of the whole AB need
    not equal xy
  • For example, suppose that completing a marathon
    has some intrinsic value, and that the pleasure
    that results of having done so also has some
    value it need not be the case that the value of
    being satisfied for having run a marathon is a
    sum of those values were one to get the same
    pleasure for having taken a delusion pill, it
    would have little value, as would joylessly
    completing a marathon
  • Note that if something contributes to the
    intrinsic value of a whole as a part, its value
    is not instrumental completing a marathon is
    not a means to the satisfaction for having done
    so, since the satisfaction could not exist
    without its object

13
Examples of Organic Unities
  • Compare the following states of affairs
  • John robs a bank (bad)
  • John robs a bank (bad) and gets 10 years in
    prison (bad)
  • Here, the addition of a bad thing seems to make
    the whole better
  • Dara is pleased (good) at the thought that Kelly
    is suffering (neutral)
  • Dara is pleased (good) at the thought that Kelly
    is happy (neutral)
  • Here the value of the whole seems to vary even
    though the value of the parts remains the same

14
The Isolation Test
  • How can we figure out what is valuable in itself
    and not as a means to something else?
  • Moore consider whether the thing would be
    valuable if it existed all by itself
  • This way we can sort out things that are valuable
    to us only because they are necessary for
    producing good things in the actual world
  • For example, we can see that we
  • We can also compare degrees of intrinsic value by
    comparing the value of isolated instances
  • This helps to see organic unities
  • For example, we can compare the value of the
    pleasure we get from contemplating art and the
    value of enjoying the same art, where enjoyment
    of x entails that x exists, but pleasure doesnt

15
Objections to the Isolation Test
  • Can we really imagine a world in which nothing
    but, say, democracy exists, and make confident
    assessments of its value?
  • Dancy the test fails to distinguish between
    parts of valuable wholes and things that enable
    other things to have value
  • A fake friendship would not be valuable, but not
    being a sham is not a feature that contributes to
    the value of genuine friendship it only enables
    the other features of friendship to give it value

16
Knowing What Is Intrinsically Good
  • When we understand the question about the good
    correctly and guard against errors due to the
    naturalistic fallacy or neglect of organic
    unities, the answer is obvious or self-evident
    no one will doubt it
  • All we can do to convince someone of the truth of
    an intrinsic value claim is to point out as
    clearly as possible what it means and how it fits
    with other propositions that appear to be equally
    true but this is not a matter of providing
    evidence or reasons for the claim

17
Moore on the Good
  • By far the most valuable things, which we know
    or can imagine, are certain states of
    consciousness, which may be roughly described as
    the pleasures of human intercourse and the
    enjoyment of beautiful objects. No one, probably,
    who has asked himself the question, has ever
    doubted that personal affection and the
    appreciation of what is beautiful in Art or
    Nature, are good in themselves nor, if we
    consider strictly what things are worth having
    purely for their own sakes, does it appear
    probable that any one will think that anything
    else has nearly so great a value as the things
    which are included under these two heads.
    (Principia, 188-189)
  • These greatest goods are organic unities

18
II From Good to Right
19
The Priority Question
  • Our moral concepts divide into two classes,
    evaluative (good, bad, courageous, lewd) and
    deontic (right, wrong, ought, reason)
  • Roughly, we use evaluative concepts to describe
    people, things, and actions, while deontic
    concepts are used to direct action
  • What is the relationship between these classes of
    concepts? Are some concepts more fundamental than
    others? Further, what is the relationship between
    the properties they pick out?

20
Moore on the Right
  • Moore believed that right actions were those that
    produce most good
  • To assert that a certain line of conduct is, at
    a given time, absolutely right or obligatory, is
    obviously to assert that more good or less evil
    will exist in the world, if it be adopted than if
    anything else be done instead. (Principia
    Ethica, 25)
  • Thus, in deciding what we ought to or have reason
    to do, we have to make two kinds of judgments
  • Causal judgments about the likely consequences of
    available alternative actions
  • Judgments about the value of the possible actions
    themselves and their consequences
  • Two perspectives deliberation and assessment

21
Natural Properties, Value, and Reasons
  • Moores view thus has the following structure
    value is a non-natural property that is
    consequential upon natural base properties, and
    we have reason to care about something because it
    has value
  • Contrast Scanlons buck-passing account of value
  • Positive thesis for something to be good is just
    for it to have base properties that give us
    reason to care about it goodness is thus merely
    a formal higher-order property
  • Negative thesis somethings being good gives us
    no additional reason to care about it
  • Thus, the buck gets passed from value to base
    properties that give us reasons to care about the
    object and (thus) make it good
  • Thus, we have metaphysical parsimony instead of
    value, natural properties, and reasons, all we
    have to explain are natural properties and
    reasons

22
Arguments for Buck-Passing
  • Explaining the openness of OQA the reason why we
    can accept for any N that x has N and yet ask
    but is it good? is that thinking that x is good
    is taking properties N to give us reason to care
    about it, and merely taking something to have N
    is not yet to draw this conclusion
  • So, when I wonder whether pleasure is good, I am
    wondering if I have reason to pursue it, and this
    kind of wondering always makes sense
  • There is no explanatory work to be done for
    goodness over and above the natural properties of
    the object
  • I have reason to go to a holiday resort because
    it is cheap, serves tasty food, favoured by the
    sort of people I like, and so on. Its being good
    gives no additional reason it is these very
    things that make it good.
  • There is no single reason-giving property of
    goodness common to all the different things we
    care about rather, reasons to care are given by
    different natural properties in different cases
  • If the Moorean view were correct, my reason to
    care about football and abstract art would be
    given by the same property, their goodness

23
Arguments Against Buck-Passing
  • Cant we imagine that something is good without
    anyone having any reason to care about it?
  • Dancy reasons are always someones reasons, but
    something can be good, period
  • Crisp suppose that all reasons derive from
    self-interest in that case, it is implausible
    that we have reason to care about all (morally)
    good things
  • Cant we have reason to care about something
    without it being good? (The wrong kind or reasons
    problem)
  • Rabinowicz and Ronnow-Rasmussen imagine an evil
    demon tells us to admire it or face endless pain
    you seem to have reason to admire it, but does
    that make it good?

24
Radical and Moderate Anti-Mooreanism
  • The buck-passing account is a radical rejection
    of defining the right in terms of the good
  • A moderate rejection asserts merely that there
    are other grounds of duty than promoting value
  • Methodological intuitionism is moderate in this
    sense

25
Two Senses of Intuitionism
  • Epistemological intuitionism
  • The foundationalist view in moral epistemology,
    according to which basic moral propositions are
    self-evident
  • Both Moore and Ross were epistemological
    intuitionists
  • Methodological intuitionism
  • The normative view according which there is a
    plurality of moral principles that cannot be
    derived from a more basic principle
  • Ross is a methodological intuitionist, but Moore
    isnt
  • A better term for methodological intuitionism is
    pluralism

26
Three Levels of Moral Judgment
  • Particular judgments
  • Ascriptions of moral properties to particular
    objects of evaluation John is an honest man
  • General judgments
  • Ascriptions of moral properties to act- or
    situation-types Stealing money from the
    collection box is wrong
  • Moral principles
  • Rules that ground other types of judgments and
    cannot themselves be derived from anything more
    fundamental Right actions are those that
    maximize the good

27
The Role of Moral Theory
  • One way to understand the business of normative
    moral theorizing is to see it as an attempt to
  • systematize and explain our particular judgments
  • by constructing more general rules and principles
    that
  • help resolve conflicts in particular cases
  • Monists like Moore, Sidgwick, and Kant believe
    that we end up with one fundamental moral
    principle, while pluralists like Ross think that
    we are left with a plurality of fundamental
    principles
  • Moore was, of course, a pluralist about value,
    since he thinks more than one kind of property
    grounds intrinsic value

28
Ross Against Consequentialism
  • The basic objection for consequentialists, the
    only morally relevant relationship is that
    between a benefactor and recipient
  • In their desire to systematize, consequentialists
    oversimplify the structure of morality
  • Rossian pluralists thus do not reject the project
    of systematizing ethics, as some claim they
    just think monism simplifies at the expense of
    truth Loyalty to the facts is worth more than a
    symmetrical architectonic or a hastily reached
    simplicity. (The Right and the Good, 23)
  • But there are other morally relevant
    relationships, and correspondingly other
    obligations
  • Others may also stand to me in the relation of
    promisee to promiser, of creditor to debtor, of
    wife to husband, of child to parent, of friend to
    friend, or fellow countryman to fellow
    countryman, and the like and each of these
    relations is the foundation of a prima facie
    duty (19)
  • Duties have a highly personal character (22)

29
The Case of Promises
  • First objection the binding force of promises is
    backward-looking, not based on the consequences
    of carrying it out
  • Even if it were always the case that keeping
    promises would maximize the good, that would be
    the wrong kind of reason to do so
  • Suppose the following is the case
  • I have promised Jane to take her to the airport,
    and that all things considered, this would
    produce 1000 units of the good
  • However, I could also play with some orphans,
    which would, all things considered (including the
    harm caused to Jane by having to call a taxi),
    produce 1001 units of the good
  • Ross To produce the 1001 units of good for B
    rather than fulfil our promise to A would eb to
    take, not perhaps our duty as philanthropists too
    seriously, but certainly our duty as makers of
    promises too lightly. (35)

30
Prima Facie Duties and Final Duty
  • Ross distinguishes between
  • prima facie duties, which are factors weighing in
    potentially different directions in a particular
    case, and ones
  • actual duty in a particular case, which is what
    one ought to do on balance
  • It turns out that prima facie duty is a
    misnomer it would be better to speak of pro
    tanto duties or reasons
  • The difference is that a prima facie duty is only
    an apparent duty, while a pro tanto reason is a
    real reason that may just be overridden in a
    particular case without ceasing to be in force
  • Thus, if you have promised to return an essay by
    Saturday and you end up having to take care of a
    sick friend, you may have done the overall right
    thing, but you still owe an explanation and maybe
    an apology the promissory obligation is
    outweighed, not cancelled
  • Since pro tanto duties are also actual, a better
    term for Rosss actual duty is final duty

31
Prima Facie Duties According to Ross
  • Duties based on my previous actions
  • Duties of fidelity based on promise or analogous
    commitment
  • Duties of reparation based on having done
    something wrong
  • Duties based on actions of others
  • Duties of gratitude based on the good others
    have done for me
  • Duties based on the possibility of changing the
    distribution of good and bad things
  • Duties of justice based on the need for rewards
    to be proportional to merit
  • Duties based on the possibility of bringing about
    good or bad things
  • Duties of beneficence
  • Duties of self-improvement
  • Duties of non-maleficence

32
Prima Facie Duties and Moral Conflict
  • Understanding prima facie duties as pro tanto
    ones is essential to understanding moral conflict
  • When two prima facie duties conflict, it is
    possible that the outweighed one gives rise to a
    derivative duty and proper regret
  • When we think ourselves justified in breaking,
    and indeed morally obliged to break, a promise in
    order to relieve some ones distress, we do not
    for a moment cease to recognize a prima facie
    duty to keep our promise, and this leads us to
    feel, not indeed shame or repentance, but
    certainly compunction, for behaving as we do we
    recognize, further, that it is our duty to make
    up somehow to the promisee for the breaking of
    the promise. (28)
  • This is hard to make sense of on monistic
    accounts why should we feel compunction for not
    doing something that we believe would have
    brought about less good anyway?

33
Knowing Prima Facie Duties
  • Prima facie duties are self-evident
  • That an act, qua fulfilling a promise, or qua
    effecting a just distribution of good ... is
    prima facie right, is self-evident not in the
    sense that it is evident from the beginning of
    our lives, or as soon as we attend to the
    proposition for the first time, but in the sense
    that when we have reached sufficient mental
    maturity and have given sufficient attention to
    the proposition it is evident without any need of
    proof ... It is evident just as a mathematical
    axiom, or the validity of a form of inference, is
    evident. (The Right and the Good, 29-30)
  • So, Ross believes that anyone who genuinely
    understands the propositions concerning prima
    facie duties and focuses on them is justified in
    believing in them
  • Compare a line is the shortest distance between
    two points if p, then q, p, so q

34
Intuitive Induction
  • Although Ross believes that verdicts on
    particular cases are not self-evident, he also
    thinks that one may come to see a self-evident
    principle of prima facie duty on the basis of
    cases
  • What comes first in time is the apprehension of
    the self-evident prima facie rightness of an
    individual act of a particular type. From this we
    come by reflection to apprehend the self-evident
    general principle of prima facie duty. (33,
    emphasis AK)
  • Verdicts on particular cases may be temporally or
    genetically prior without being logically prior
  • What is meant to be self-evident is that a
    particular aspect of a particular action gives a
    pro tanto reason for or against doing it

35
Knowing the Final Duty
  • Final duty is a result of the interaction of the
    prima facie duties bearing on the situation
  • Since the kind and stringency of prima facie
    duties varies with situation, final duty isnt a
    priori knowable or self-evident in the end,
    the discernment rests with perception
    (Aristotle)
  • These judgments are neither self-evident nor
    deductible from self-evident premises
  • There is no priority ordering among the prima
    facie duties that is, it is not the case that
    duties of justice, say, are always weightier than
    duties of beneficence
  • Compare to assessing a poem even if we know that
    naivete is always bad and insightfulness always
    good (and are able to tell when these obtain), we
    cannot calculate its value on the basis of such
    contributory principles

36
Limits of Moral Theory
  • A basic objection to intuitionism it only
    mirrors the complexity of ordinary moral thought
    and offers no help in resolving conflicts
  • McNaughton this is an unrealistic expectation
    The job of a moral theory is simply to see which
    general account of the nature of our duties (and
    of goodness) gives the best overall picture of
    our moral thinking. There is no question of
    theory revealing answers to moral questions that
    cannot otherwise be answered. (An Unconnected
    Heap of Duties?, 90)

37
III Intuitionism as Foundationalist Moral
Epistemology
38
What is Justification?
  • There are many different notions of
    justification, of which the following two are
    most pertinent to moral epistemology
  • Agent justification When an agent A has agent
    justification for believing p, she is
    epistemically blameless for taking p to be true
  • Demonstrative justification A has demonstrative
    justification when she can present grounds that
    can rationally convince others that she has agent
    justification for p
  • It is possible to have agent justification
    without demonstrative justification
  • For example, a child who sees an ice cream truck
    may be justified in believing that there is an
    ice cream truck in front of her, even though she
    is not able to present grounds for believing so
    (such as cite the reliability of eyesight in
    detecting middle-sized objects)
  • On realist views, justification doesnt entail
    truth
  • That is, we may be justified in holding false
    beliefs

39
Inferential Justification
  • As belief that p is inferentially justified when
    p is supported by the content of As other
    justified beliefs, say q and r
  • For example, my belief that Jacob is at home is
    justified when I hold it on the basis of
    believing that Jacob just answered the phone and
    believing that if someone picks up the phone,
    they are at home
  • Views about the sort of support needed for
    justification vary on strictest views, p must
    deductively follow from q and r
  • On less stringent views, making p probable is
    enough
  • q and r are, in one sense of the term, reasons
    for believing p

40
Foundationalism and the Regress Argument
  • The aim of the Regress Argument is to show that
    not all justification can be inferential
  • Assume that all justification is inferential
  • Then q can justify p only if q itself is
    justified by some further proposition r
  • But r, in turn, must be justified by some yet
    further proposition x, and so on ad infinitum
  • As finite beings, we cannot complete an infinite
    chain of justification, so we are not justified
    in believing anything including the proposition
    that all justification is inferential. But this
    is absurd.
  • Thus, there must be beliefs that are
    non-inferentially justified

41
Non-Inferential Justification
  • The essential thesis of foundationalism is thus
    that there are some justified beliefs that do not
    derive their justification from other justified
    beliefs there is nothing further we could cite
    as a reason for them
  • This leaves open several sources of justification
  • Direct acquintance with facts
  • Non-conceptual sense data
  • Reliable subpersonal information-processing
  • Self-evidence
  • The main alternative response to the regress
    argument is denying that inferential
    justification must be linear that is,
    justification doesnt always derive from some
    further belief, but can be a matter of mutual
    support
  • Well return to this in Lecture 8

42
The Idea of Self-Evidence
  • A proposition is self-evident when understanding
    and attentively considering it is sufficient for
    being justified in believing in it, and for
    knowing it if one believes it on the basis of
    such understanding
  • Note the following consequences
  • One is justified in believing in the truth of the
    proposition, which is different from believing in
    its self-evidence a child who lacks the concept
    of self-evidence can still be justified in
    believing that 224
  • This definition of self-evidence does not rule
    out that one has also inferential justification
    for the proposition it simply says that
    inferential justification is not necessary

43
Experience and Self-Evidence
  • Although experience does not play an evidential
    role in justifying self-evident beliefs, it can
    still play an enabling role
  • That is, one may not adequately understand a
    proposition without suitable experience
  • For example, one may not count as grasping a
    proposition like Breaking a promise is pro tanto
    wrong simply by being able to put the words
    together in some simple contexts
  • Nothing rules out that emotions might play an
    evidential role in adequate understanding

44
Conclusions of Inference and Conclusions of
Reflection
  • A conclusion of inference is made on the basis of
    reasons that support the judgment
  • For example, one concludes that a painting is by
    Picasso as a result of examining the paint used
    and the characteristic hand movements visible on
    the surface
  • A conclusion of reflection emerges from thinking
    about a whole and the relationship between its
    parts
  • For example, one concludes that a painting is
    moving after carefully examining and
    contemplating it
  • Conclusions of reflection are responses to
    patterns in things that defy codification in
    terms of rules (A painting is moving if it
    employs sharp contrasts between dark and light
    colours)
  • Audi an intuitive judgment may be a conclusion
    of reflection, which means that it may take time
    and effort and so fail to seem self-evident or
    true to the agent

45
Candidates for Self-Evident Propositions
  • Nothing can be both red and green all over
  • The existence of great-grandchildren is
    impossible without at least four generations of
    people
  • If p, then q not-q so not-p is a necessarily
    truth-preserving inference
  • Other things being equal, pleasure is a good
    thing
  • Other things being equal, that an arrangement
    would benefit cheaters is a reason to oppose it

46
Objections to Moral Intuitionism I
  • I dont find these propositions self-evident!
  • Reply to disagreement about self-evidence
  • The claim isnt that anyone who understands that
    propositions finds them self-evident, but that
    they are justified in believing in them
  • Believing that a proposition is self-evident is a
    second-order attitude toward it that requires
    grasping a further concept, namely the concept of
    self-evidence itself

47
Objections to Moral Intuitionism II
  • But I dont even believe in these propositions,
    even though I perfectly understand them! In fact,
    I think theyre false!
  • Reply to lack of belief and disagreement about
    truth
  • One need not believe a self-evident proposition
    even on understanding it the definition simply
    says that one is justified if one so believes
  • People may reject self-evident truths because
    they are in the grip of a view that is
    incompatible with them
  • You cant convince everyone
  • J R Lucas If I was arguing with a man, and he
    did not allow that causing pain was a reason for
    an actions being wrong, that is, he did not see
    the relevance of that fact that the action caused
    pain, I think I should break off the argument
    with him... Sadists need to be cured rather than
    convinced. (Ethical Intuitionism II, 9-10)

48
Objections to Moral Intuitionism III
  • But it is dogmatic to just ignore anyone who
    disagrees and thump the table!
  • Reply to the dogmatism charge
  • An intuitionist can grant that the existence of
    disagreement among reasonable people gives reason
    to doubt a proposition that seems self-evident
    (or just true) one needs to go back and check
    if one has really understood it correctly, if it
    really is basic, and so on
  • Thus, intuitionism doesnt entitle one to be
    dogmatic
  • At the same time, the difference between agent
    justification and demonstrative justification
    means that one may not be able to demonstrate
    justification that one nonetheless has

49
Objections to Moral Intuitionism IV
  • But it is intolerably conservative to just
    certify our existing moral convictions as they
    stand!
  • Reply to the conservatism objection
  • Propositions that seem self-evident can lose
    their justification on further reflection, but
    here, as elsewhere, appearances can be rejected
    only on the basis of further appearances of the
    same kind
  • We have no more direct way of access to facts
    about rightness and goodness and about what
    things are good, than by thinking about them the
    moral convictions of thoughtful and well-educated
    people are the data of ethics just as
    sense-perceptions are the data of a natural
    science. (Ross, 40-41)
  • Just as some of the latter have to be rejected
    as illusory, so have some of the former but as
    the latter are rejected only when they are in
    conflict with other more accurate
    sense-perceptions, the former are rejected only
    when they are in conflict with other convictions
    which stand better the test of reflection. (41)

50
Objections to Moral Intuitionism V
  • Im an instrumentalist about practical reason,
    so I think we only have reason to take the best
    means to any given end of ours. Therefore, I
    reject the claim that everyone has a pro tanto
    reason not to injure others!
  • Reply to the objection from instrumentalism
  • But what, then, is the status of the instrumental
    principle (rationality requires taking the
    necessary means to ones ends) itself?
  • It is not an empirical truth but a normative one
  • Audi Unless reason has sufficient power to make
    principles like Rosss candidates for truth, then
    it is not clear that instrumentalist principles
    are candidates either (Moderate Intuitionism,
    34)

51
Skepticism and Partners in Crime
  • Shafer-Landau If you reject the self-evidence of
    basic moral propositions, youll have to reject a
    lot more
  • The same arguments would apply to philosophical
    intuitions as well
  • Audi distinction between rebutting and refuting
    skepticism we can do the former
  • Rebutting skepticism is showing that the grounds
    for it are unsound removing justification from
    skepticism itself
  • Refuting skepticism is showing that it is false
    by providing positive justification for the
    original view
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com