Overview of Significant Ethical Approaches on how to - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 368
About This Presentation
Title:

Overview of Significant Ethical Approaches on how to

Description:

Virtue Ethics Plato Aristotle Misconceptions Regarding Virtue Ethics John Dewey Kant Social Contract Ethics Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill Rule vs. Act Utilitarianism – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:1146
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 369
Provided by: Shoc
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Overview of Significant Ethical Approaches on how to


1
Overview of Significant Ethical Approaches on how
to find Moral Truth
  1. Virtue Ethics
  2. Plato
  3. Aristotle
  4. Misconceptions Regarding Virtue Ethics
  5. John Dewey
  6. Kant
  7. Social Contract Ethics
  8. Utilitarianism
  9. John Stuart Mill
  10. Rule vs. Act Utilitarianism
  11. Act Utilitarianism
  12. Kantian Utilitarianism (R. M. Hare)
  13. G. E. Moores Utilitarianism
  14. Intuitionism
  15. Ethical Relativism
  16. Moral Realism
  17. Care Ethics
  18. F. Nietzsche
  19. David Hume

2
Welcome to Ethics
  • Unless your faculties arent working properly,
    you have an interest in ethics and the reason why
    is simple
  • Ethics is about what is right and what is wrong
    and how can we tell the difference.

3
Consider the following questions
  • What does it mean to be moral?
  • What are human beings really like selfish,
    greedy, noble, or good?
  • Are some people better at being good than
    others? If so, how and why?
  • What does it mean to be good?
  • Are there good ways of teaching children to
    behave morally?
  • Does anyone have the right to tell anyone else
    what is right from wrong?
  • What is human nature?

4
Consider the following questions
  • Why should I be a good person? What does it mean
    to be a good person?
  • Is morality about obeying a set of rules or is it
    about thinking carefully about consequences?
  • When people say cannibalism is wrong, do they
    know it is wrong or just believe it very
    strongly?
  • Are there certain kinds of acts that are always
    wrong (e.g., torturing children, beating up your
    mother, lying)?
  • Is it okay to ever break a law?
  • Is it wrong to enjoy hurting others?
  • Are human beings essentially good or essentially
    wicked?

5
How do you find ethical, moral truth?
Plato Kant say the power of reason
Jainism says ascetic control/suppression of all
feelings.
Sir W. D. Ross says intuitions
H. Utilitarians say we discover the right act
calculating the balance of pleasure over pain
Virtue Ethics says in a virtuous character
whereby a person is able to realize the crucial
potentialities that constitute human excellence.
Its focus is on the person rather than the act.
Nonobject. say there is no truth
Social contract theorists say ethical principles
are made, not found, constructed by social
groups, and exists for the benefit of those
groups.
Care Ethics Narrative of relationships that
extend through time.
Natural/Special Revelation from God
6
Overview of Ethical Systems Virtue Ethics
Rather than focusing on what we ought to do,
Virtue ethics offers a distinctive approach
whereby we focus on human character asking the
question, What should I be? Thus, ethical life
involves envisioning ideals for human life and
embodying those ideals in ones life. Virtues
are ways in which we embody those ideals.
Plato (c.427-347c) To be virtuous we must
understand what contributes to our overall good
have our desire (appetitive workers), spirit
(warriors), reason (ruler-guardians) educated
properly so they will aggregate with the guidance
provided by the rational part of the soul (Books
2 3 of Republic). When these 3 parts of the
soul conflict with each other, it might move us
to act in ways that go against the greater good
(become incontinent).
Virtue is an excellence of some sort. Originally
the word meant strength and referred to as
manliness. In Aristotles ethics (arete) is
used which is trans. as excellences of various
types.
Plato (c. 427-347) is concerned with the quality
of a persons inner state he prized beauty,
health, harmony, strength of a soul as the
virtues we should emulate. Aristotle (384-322)
The function of man is reason (the good of the
thing is when it performs its function well)
which is peculiar to him. Thus, the function of
man is reason and the life that is distinctive of
humans is the life in accordance with reason. If
the function of man is reason, then the good man
is the man who reasons well This is the life of
excellence (eudaimonia human flourishing
well-being). G.E.M. Anscombe (1919-2001) argues
we cant rely on moral obligation using a
non-religious ethic but we can rely on the Greek
notion of excellence because it is tied to
well-being appropriateness to the kind of
things we are. Philippa Foot (1920-) ethical
naturalist, grounds the virtues in what is good
for human beings the virtues are beneficial to
their possessor or to the community virtues are
valuable because they contribute to it.
Aristotle says there are 2 types of virtue
intellectual virtues excellences of the mind
(e.g., ability to understand, reason, judge
well) moral virtues learned by repetition
(e.g., practicing honesty we become honest. To be
virtuous requires knowledge, practice,
consistent effort at character building.
Aristotle Must have knowledge, second he must
choose the acts and choose them for their own
sakes, finally his actions must proceed from a
firm character (1105a).
7
Basic Framework of Virtue Ethics
  • Premise 1 An action is right iff it is what a
    virtuous agent would do in the circumstances.
  • Premise 1a A virtuous agent is one who acts
    virtuously, i.e., one who has and exercises the
    virtues.
  • Premise 2 A virtue is a character trait a human
    being needs to flourish or live well.

8
3 Central Concepts
  • Though there are several modern versions of
    virtue ethics, most models have their roots in
    ancient Greek philosophy by the employment of
    three concepts derived from it
  • 1. arête (excellence or virtue)
  • 2. phronesis (practical or moral wisdom)
  • 3. eudaimonia (usually translated as human)
    flourishing successful living)

9
Consider the following quote
  • We are discussing no small matter, but how we
    ought to live.
  • Socrates in Platos Republic

10
Overview of Ethical Systems Plato (427-347
B.C.)
Plato believed our natural desires are greedy and
depraved. Thus, they must be held in tight
check by the powers of reason. He compared the
human soul to a city-state made up of
ruler-guardians, guardians, and the
peasants/artisans. Every reality is an
archetype of a corresponding eternal form. The
goal of life is to actualize ones true nature
together with ones many innate potentialities.
So long as the individual is governed by the
power of reason, and reason is assisted by
courage and will power (guardians), the unruly
desires can be suppressed.
If reason for a moment lets down its guard, then
the desires will exert their power, seize
control, and lead the person to corruption and
immorality.
The highest good is the well-ordered whole to
which each part contributes according to its own
capacity. A thing in reality is good insofar as
it participates in corresponds to the form of
the good (which is the high point of the forms).
4 primary integrated virtues Wisdom corresponds
to reason courage corresponds to the will
temperance, corresponds to desire justice
links individual to society.
11
Essential Terms for Plato
  • 1. teleology "everything in the universe has a
    proper function to perform within a harmonious
    hierarchy of purposes"
  • 2. reason the intellectual component of the
    soul "calculates, measures and decides"
  • 3. spirit "structural element of the soul" this
    is our passionate side that desires honor, glory,
    and respect
  • appetite the part of the soul that desires
    things that help us to satisfy our biological and
    material desires
  • moral balance situation in which reason governs
    the soul guarding against the excesses of spirit
    and appetite.
  • 6. class system In Plato's Republic, a way of
    dividing individuals into different social groups
    based on their talents. There are three classes
    philosopher-kings (rulers reason ), auxiliaries
    (guardians spirit) who serve as warriors, and a
    combination of craftsmen, artisans, and traders
    who are driven mostly by appetite.
  • 7. just society a society that functions
    harmoniously by allowing each individual to do
    the work suited to his/her talents.
  • 8. philosopher kings rulers in Plato's just
    society from the Republic
  • 9. guardian class warriors in Plato's just
    society from the Republic

12
Main Points to Know
  • Plato writes dialogues rather than philosophical
    treatises. Hence, most of his philosophical
    positions are voiced through the character of
    Socrates. Even though Socrates was Plato's actual
    teacher, the positions and doctrines
    traditionally attributed to Socrates are actually
    Plato's account of his teacher. Socrates never
    wrote anything.
  • Plato advances a teleological conception of
    morality, "we live the good life insofar as we
    perform our distinctively human function well."

13
Main Points to Know
  • The soul is divided into three parts appetitive,
    spirit, and reason. Each part helps us to fulfill
    critical needs, but in Plato's view, only the
    rational part of the soul is fit to rule.
  • In order to live a virtuous life, it is necessary
    for the individual to cultivate balance in
    his/her soul. Thus, persons ruled by appetite or
    spirit (emotion) are "out of balance" and their
    actions are apt to provoke personal or social
    disharmony.

14
Main Points to Know
  • Appetite In cases where appetite rules
    (oligarchic and tyrannical characters fit here)
    individuals are at the mercy of the their
    biological or material whims. Alcohol addiction
    fits this profile. Individuals who are addicted
    to self-destructive patterns of behavior are apt
    to feed their appetites at the expense of other
    life pursuits. People can also be ruled by
    material greed in much the same way. The key here
    is that desire is determinative these are
    cravings of the highest degree.

15
Main Points to Know
  • Spirit The emotional, passionate side of our
    character is centered on the idea of status on a
    social level. Ambition, desire for honor and
    glory, moral indignation, and cravings for
    admiration, all fit under the umbrella of spirit.
    Love relationships fit into this category as
    well. Our interactions with others provide core
    experiences that influence our emotional
    development.

16
Main Points to Know
  • Reason The intellectual, thinking part of the
    soul that must weigh options, decide between
    alternatives, and "suppress dangerous urges.
    Plato clearly puts reason in control of the soul
    because it acts as good counsel seeking
    understanding and insight before acting. Rational
    individuals possess a strong contemplative
    faculty. They think before they act and are
    unlikely to take rash action in any given
    situation.

17
Know Thyself
  • Plato contends that each one of us performs/does
    one thing best. We each have one best skill and
    it is the development of this skill that is of
    paramount importance in creating a harmonious
    existence. If we do not have insight into what
    we do best, the chances of achieving a balanced
    soul are likely reduced. Hence the Socratic
    imperative, "know thyself."
  • Just Society First ask yourself is it possible
    to have a just society? What would it look like?
    How would we direct education, the economy,
    leisure, and social resources? What is fair?
  • Plato wrestles with the idea of justice in his
    most famous work entitled, The Republic.

18
Plato views social justice exactly parallels his
notion of individual justice. There are three
parts of the soul and three corresponding
divisions in the social order. The social order
is constructed as follows
SOCIETY
SOUL
Reason
Philosopher-King
Spirit
Auxiliaries/Guardians
Appetite
Craftsmen/Artisans/Traders
19
Three Elements in the Soul that are distinguished
by their functions, goal, and activities
  • Reason-calculation calculates calculation is
    concerned with the good (i.e., with the best
    course of action)
  • Appetite-Desire desires Desire is concerned with
    pleasure
  • Spirit gets spirited spirit reacts to perceived
    slights or wrong.
  • When you revisit these elements in Books 8-8,
    they no longer look like faculties (as they did
    in book 4) they now seem more like drives. The
    desiring element is specified as the drive toward
    material satisfaction spirit as the drive to win
    and to amount to something calculation as the
    drive to discover truth.

20
Interestingly
  • By Book 9 the calculative element has a goal of
    its own seeks wisdom. Wisdom is a good, of
    course, arguably the highest good. But this
    element seeks wisdom because it is wisdom, not
    because it is good. It has turned out to be the
    philosophical element in the soul. For this
    reason we should not be content for the
    calculative element merely to supervise within
    us, not if we want to be happy. Its natural
    passion is directed at something different and
    better than this. Certainly, it is better that
    this element in each person should be supervisor
    than that it should fall under the control of the
    other elements of the soul and be reduced to a
    tool in their service, as described in Books 8
    and 9. But although it is appropriate that the
    calculative element should supervise the others
    (44Ie), this is not what it loves to do. As the
    philosophical element in the soul, it takes on
    the job of ruling the soul with a reserve
    comparable in some respects to that with which
    philosophers take on the job of ruling the city.
    Even with the soul, ruling is work.the
    philosophical element is divine and immortal, the
    other elements are mortal and animal, and only
    the necessity of incarnation thrusts them
    together.
  • Cambridge Companion to Platos Republic,
    Three-Part Soul by G. R. F. Ferrari, pg. 166.

21
An Ideal City
  • Plato attempts to show that on justice is so
    great a good that it is worth any sacrifice. He
    portrays an ideal political community there we
    will see justice writ large, and so we will be
    better able to find justice in the individual
    soul. An ideal city must make radical
    innovations. It should be ruled by specially
    trained philosophers, since their understanding
    of the Form of the Good will give them greater
    insight into everyday affairs. Their education
    is compared to that of a prisoner who, having
    once gazed upon nothing but shadows in the
    artificial light of a cave, is released from
    bondage, leaves the cave, eventually learns to
    see the sun, and is thereby equipped to return to
    the cave and see the images there for what the
    are. Everything in the rulers lives is designed
    to promote their allegiance to the community
    they are forbidden private possessions, their
    sexual lives are regulated by eugenic
    considerations, and they are not to know who
    their children art. Positions of political power
    are open to women, since the physical differences
    between them and men do not in all cases deprive
    them of the intellectual or moral capacities
    needed for political office. The works of poets
    are to be carefully regulated, for the false
    moral notions of the traditional poets have had a
    powerful and deleterious impact on the general
    public. Philosophical reflection is to replace
    popular poetry as the force that guides moral
    education.

22
An Ideal City
  • What makes this city ideally just is the
    dedication of each of its components to one task
    for which it is naturally suited and specially
    trained. The rulers are ideally equipped to
    rule the soldiers are best able to enforce their
    commands and the economic class, composed of
    farmers, craftsmen, builders, etc. are content to
    do their work and to leave the tasks of making
    and enforcing the laws to others.

23
What makes the soul of person just?
  • What makes the soul of a human being just is the
    same principle each of its components must
    properly perform its own task. The part of us
    that is capable of understanding and reasoning is
    the part that must rule the assertive part that
    makes us capable of anger and competitive spirit
    must give our understanding the force it needs
    and our appetites for food and sex must be
    trained so that they seek only those objects that
    reason approves. It is not enough to educate
    someones reasons, for unless the emotions and
    appetites are properly trained they will
    overpower it. Just individuals are those who
    have fully integrated these elements of the soul.

24
What makes the soul of person just?
  • Just individuals are those who have fully
    integrated these elements of the soul. They do
    not unthinkingly follow a list of rules rather,
    their just treatment of others flow from their
    own balanced psychological condition. And the
    paradigm of a just person is a philosopher, for
    reason rules when it becomes passionately
    attached to the most intelligible object there
    are the Forms (which are eternal, changeless,
    and imperceptible). It emerges that justice pays
    because attachment to these supremely valuable
    objects is part of what true justice of the soul
    is. The worth of our lives depends on the worth
    of objects to which we devote ourselves. Those
    who think that injustice pays assume that wealth,
    domination, or the pleasures of the physical
    appetite are supremely valuable their mistake
    lies in their limited conception of what sorts of
    objects are worth loving.

25
The Forms
  • 1. Phaedo is the first dialogue in which Plato
    decisively posits the existence of the abstract
    objects that he often called Forms or
    Ideas-which exist independently of thought
    (eidos and idea).
  • Forms are eternal, changeless, and incorporeal.
    Since they are imperceptible we can come to have
    knowledge of them only through thought.
  • a. Beautiful roses is not Beauty itself.
  • b. What every rose has in common with every
    other is that it bears a certain
    relationship-called participation-to one and
    the same thing, the Form of Beauty. Thus, what
    makes roses beautiful is the unchanging
    Form-beauty.
  • 3. For Plato the Forms are not merely an unusual
    item to be added to our list of existing objects.
    Rather, they are a source of inspiration and
    their discovery is a decisive turning point in
    ones life.

26
Example from Symposium Love.
  • According to Diotimas account, those who are in
    love are searching for something they do not yet
    understand whether they realize it or not, they
    seek the eternal possession of the good, and they
    can obtain it only through productive activity of
    some sort. Physical love perpetuates the species
    and achieves a lower form of immortality, but a
    more beautiful kind of offspring is produced by
    those who govern cities and shape the moral
    characteristics of future generations.

27
Example from Symposium Love.
  • Best of all is the kind of love that eventually
    attaches itself to the Form of Beauty, since this
    is the most beautiful of objects and provides the
    greatest happiness to the lover. One develops a
    love for this Form by ascending through various
    stages of emotional attachment and understanding.
    Beginning with an attraction to the beauty of
    one persons body, one gradually develops an
    appreciation for the beauty present in all other
    beautiful bodies then ones recognition of the
    beauty in peoples souls takes on increasing
    strength, and leads to a deeper attachment to the
    beauty of customs, laws, and systems of
    knowledge and this process of emotional growth
    and deepening insight culminates in the discovery
    of the eternal and changeless beauty of Beauty
    itself.

28
Aristotle Rejection of Plato
  • Platos chief contribution consists in his
    conception of the observable world as an
    imperfect image of a realm of unobservable and
    unchanging Forms, and his conception of the
    best life as one centered on the love of these
    divine objects.
  • Aristotle rejects Platos transcendental Form of
    the Good as irrelevant to the affairs of persons,
    and in general, had little sympathy with the
    notion of the absolute good. Rather, the goal of
    choice and action is the human good, namely,
    living well.

29
Aristotle Rejection of Plato
  • Platos general theory of knowledge, i.e., the
    theory of forms has much in common with the
    theories of innate ideas. What is known, at the
    highest and most general level, is a collection
    of objects, with which we have all had direct
    acquaintance prior to birth (the forms or
    ideas). All of us, therefore, may have some
    inkling of general truths but only those whose
    rational capacities are especially well
    developed-in short, philosophers-can fully
    reactivate their memories.
  • Aristotle rejects Platos theory of knowledge.
    He locates the source of ethical insight in
    experience of life itself. Aristotle argues that
    we need to know how to act, possess practical
    wisdom (have an eye for solutions)and that can
    only be developed through a combination of
    training in the right habits and direct
    acquaintance with practical situations.

30
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • Read in this way, Aristotle is engaged in a
    project similar in some respects to the one Plato
    carried out in the Republic. One of Plato's
    central points is that it is a great advantage to
    establish a hierarchical ordering of the elements
    in one's soul and he shows how the traditional
    virtues can be interpreted to foster or express
    the proper relation between reason and less
    rational elements of the psyche. Aristotle's
    approach is similar his function argument
    shows in a general way that our good lies in the
    dominance of reason, and the detailed studies of
    the particular virtues reveal how each of them
    involves the right kind of ordering of the soul.

31
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • Aristotle's goal is to arrive at conclusions
    similar to Plato's, but without relying on the
    Platonic metaphysics that plays a central role in
    the argument of the Republic. He rejects the
    existence of Plato's forms in general and the
    form of the good in particular and he rejects
    the idea that in order to become fully virtuous
    one must study mathematics and the sciences, and
    see all branches of knowledge as a unified whole.
    Even though Aristotle's ethical theory sometimes
    relies on philosophical distinctions that are
    more fully developed in his other works, he never
    proposes that students of ethics need to engage
    in a specialized study of the natural world, or
    mathematics, or eternal and changing objects. His
    project is to make ethics an autonomous field,
    and to show why a full understanding of what is
    good does not require expertise in any other
    field.

32
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • There is another contrast with Plato that should
    be emphasized In Book II of the Republic, we are
    told that the best type of good is one that is
    desirable both in itself and for the sake of its
    results (357d-358a). Plato argues that justice
    should be placed in this category, but since it
    is generally agreed that it is desirable for its
    consequences, he devotes most of his time to
    establishing his more controversial pointthat
    justice is to be sought for its own sake. By
    contrast, Aristotle assumes that if A is
    desirable for the sake of B, then B is better
    than A (1094a14-16) therefore, the highest kind
    of good must be one that is not desirable for the
    sake of anything else.

33
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • To show that A deserves to be our ultimate end,
    one must show that all other goods are best
    thought of as instruments that promote A in some
    way or other. Accordingly, it would not serve
    Aristotle's purpose to consider virtuous activity
    in isolation from all other goods. He needs to
    discuss honor, wealth, pleasure, and friendship
    in order to show how these goods, properly
    understood, can be seen as resources that serve
    the higher goal of virtuous activity. He
    vindicates the centrality of virtue in a
    well-lived life by showing that in the normal
    course of things a virtuous person will not live
    a life devoid of friends, honor, wealth,
    pleasure, and the like.

34
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • Virtuous activity makes a life happy not by
    guaranteeing happiness in all circumstances, but
    by serving as the goal for the sake of which
    lesser goods are to be pursued. Aristotle's
    methodology in ethics therefore pays more
    attention than does Plato's to the connections
    that normally obtain between virtue and other
    goods. That is why he stresses that in this sort
    of study one must be satisfied with conclusions
    that hold only for the most part (1094b11-22).
    Poverty, isolation, and dishonor are normally
    impediments to the exercise of virtue and
    therefore to happiness, although there may be
    special circumstances in which they are not. The
    possibility of exceptions does not undermine the
    point that, as a rule, to live well is to have
    sufficient resources for the pursuit of virtue
    over the course of a lifetime.

35
Aristotles Differences with Plato
  • Difference over what is virtue and vice.
  • Aristotle differs with Platos notion (early
    dialogues) that virtue is nothing but a kind of
    knowledge and vice is nothing more but a lack of
    knowledge.
  • The significance of Aristotle's characterization
    of these states as hexeis is his decisive
    rejection of that thesis. Aristotle insists that
    virtues differ from crafts and all branches of
    knowledge for they involve appropriate emotional
    responses rather than pure intellectual
    conditions.

36
Some Similarities between Plato Aristotle
  • Aristotle sees the human body as complex of
    soul and body whereas Plato sees souls
    temporarily united with bodies (Plato), they are
    like other things in the world for they have a
    function or activity which is peculiar to
    them.
  • The good life, eudaimonia, will consist in the
    successful performance of that function.
  • Nothing can perform its peculiar function
    successfully unless it possess the relevant
    arete, i.e., unless it is good of its kind (two
    platonic examples the only horses that will be
    able to win races the only pruning-knives which
    can successfully be used to cut vines-will be
    good ones).
  • For both Plato and Aristotle the content of
    arete depends on some prior notion of what it is
    to be human.

37
What is the function of human beings and what is
the arete which relates to that?
  • 1. Platos answers are, respectively, governing
    and the like (i.e., the governing of the soul by
    its union with the body), and justice.
  • 2. An active life of that which possesses
    reason, and the best of the arete.

38
Overview of Ethical Systems Aristotle (384-322
B.C.)
Though we are naturally suited to moral goodness,
we dont automatically develop such inclinations
Your habits inclinations develop with practice
what you sow is what you reap.
Carefully cultivate moral goodness by rigorous
practice.
Ideal of virtue is doing the right thing because
you want to do the right thing you desire to
act virtuously.
In order to desire to act virtuously you must
carefully and consistently practice doing right
until it becomes habitual natural.
If you act selfishly then you will become a
selfish person. Eventually what feels right to
you may be very wrong.
With practice diligence you can develop the
habits inclinations of a virtuous person.
Thus, choose to be virtuous. Desire judgment
must agree.
39
Closer Look at Virtue
  • A virtue such as honesty or generosity is not
    just a tendency to do what is honest or generous,
    nor is it to be helpfully specified as a
    "desirable" or "morally valuable" character
    trait. It is, indeed a character trait that is,
    a disposition which is well entrenched in its
    possessor, something that, as we say "goes all
    the way down", unlike a habit such as being a
    tea-drinker but the disposition in question,
    far from being a single track disposition to do
    honest actions, or even honest actions for
    certain reasons, is multi-track. It is concerned
    with many other actions as well, with emotions
    and emotional reactions, choices, values,
    desires, perceptions, attitudes, interests,
    expectations and sensibilities. To possess a
    virtue is to be a certain sort of person with a
    certain complex mindset. (Hence the extreme
    recklessness of attributing a virtue on the basis
    of a single action) Stanford Encyclopedia

40
Why do you want to be happy?
  • For Aristotle, the ultimate aim of the best life
    is eudaimonia. If someone asks why you want to
    go to college, buy a car, or get a divorce, it
    makes sense to answer that you are doing these
    things as part of a long-term plan to achieve
    happiness. But if someone asks why you want to
    be happy, there is no answer because happiness is
    not a means to anything further. Happiness is
    valuable solely for its own sake. Now, the claim
    that everything else is valued for the sake of
    happiness is somewhat more controversial
  • Mill agrees with Aristotle, but Kant thinks that
    duty is desirable solely for its own sake.
  • There is much disagreement about what happiness
    is. Some people think happiness is sensual
    pleasure others think it is wealth, honor, good
    action, or contemplation.

41
Virtue Ethics What kind of person should I be?
  • What is a virtue?
  • A virtue is a habit of excellence, a beneficial
    tendency, a skilled disposition that enables a
    person to realize the crucial potentialities that
    constitute proper human flourishing (eudaimonia).
  • What is a habit? A disposition to think, feel,
    desire, and act in a certain way without having a
    tendency to consciously will to do so.
  • What is a character The sum-total of ones
    habits, tendencies, and well-being.
  • Four cardinal virtues temperance, courage,
    prudence, and justice. Piety (reverence to the
    gods) is sometimes considered a fifth virtue.

42
On Becoming Agathos EudaimonFrom Aristotles
Point of ViewCited from Michael Boylan, Basic
Ethics (Upper Saddle River, N.J. Prentice Hall,
2000), 52.
  • Step 1 Master the functional requirements within
    a given type of task or behavior.
  • Step 2 Possess the habitual mastery of the
    functional requirements to an appropriate
    degree.
  • Step 3 Steps 1 2 excellence in that task or
    behavior.
  • Step 4 Possess habitual excellence in a number
    of key tasks or behavior.
  • Step 5 Possess habitual excellence in those
    tasks or behavior that the common opinion judges
    to be the most worthy.
  • Step 6 Steps 4 5 leads to agathos.
  • Step 7 Possessing Agathos leads to eudaimon.
  • Thus, on balance, excellent traits in human
    character generally produce excellent actions.

43
What is Virtue
  • Aristotle characterizes virtue as follows
  • Virtue, then, is a state of character, concerned
    with choice, lying in a mean, i.e., the mean
    relative to us, this being determined by
    principle, that principle by which the man of
    practical wisdom would determine it (1106b-1107).

44
  • The good for man, then, is activity in accordance
    with virtue or the highest virtue. Just like the
    excellence of an lies in cutting, a things
    excellence is a master of how well it performs
    its characteristic functions or, we might say,
    how well it realizes it nature.
  • The natural functions of persons reside in their
    exercise of their natural cognitive faculties,
    most importantly, the faculty of reason. So
    human happiness consistence in activity in
    accordance with reason. However, persons can
    exercise reason in practical or in purely
    theoretical matters. The first suggest that
    happiness consists in the practical life of moral
    virtue, the second that is consists in the life
    of theoretical activity.
  • Most of Nicomachean Ethics is devoted to moral
    virtues but final book appears to favor
    theoretical activity (theoria) as the highest and
    most choice-worthy end. It is mans closest
    approach to divine activity.
  • The fully virtuous do what they should without a
    struggle against contrary desires the continent
    have to control a desire or temptation to do
    otherwise.

45
Character
  • When Aristotle says that a virtuous persons
    virtuous acts proceed from a firm character, he
    means to distinguish virtue from other sorts of
    character. Consider
  • The acts of a virtuous person do not arise out of
    some quirk of circumstances. Rather, a virtuous
    persons acts are typical of that person because
    virtue is his/her set of habits of passion,
    desire, pleasure, thoughts, the like.
    Therefore, he/she is not out-of-character. In
    other words, the virtuous person can be counted
    on to perform such acts.

46
Character
  • 3. The acts are not the result of outside
    pressure or persuasion but come instead from
    within the person.
  • The act should not be performed by an effort of
    will against temptation. The virtuous person is
    not conflicted-not pulled one way be desire and
    another by duty. He or she is in harmony with
    himself or herself. Thus even though the
    continent person is reliably good and internally
    motivated, his/her act does not proceed from a
    firm character.
  • Consider the following chart of 6 different
    types of character

47
Aristotles Descriptions of the Various Sorts of
Characters
Character Passion/Desires
Principles/Choices Choices
Heroically virtuous very right very
right very right Virtuous right
right right Continent wrong
right right Incontinent wrong
right wrong Vicious wrong
wrong wrong Brutish very wrong
very wrong very wrong
  • 1. Heroic person possesses supererogatory
    virtue, acting feeling even better than
    ordinary virtuous people
  • 2. Virtuous person has right passions desires,
    makes right choices based on right principles,
    reliably performs right acts.
  • 3. The continent person overcomes temptation by
    will power. He has wrong passions desires but
    makes right choices performs right acts.
  • The incontinent fails to overcome temptation
    because of weakness of will he has wrong
    passions desires makes right choices but
    performs wrong acts (1150a15).
  • 5. The vicious brutish characters need no
    further explanation.

48
Character
  • Aristotle goes onto characterize virtue further
    when he states 1106b-1107
  • Virtue, then is a state of character concerned
    with choice, lying in a mean, i.e., the mean
    relative to us, this being determined by a
    rational principle, that principle by which the
    man of practical wisdom would determine it.

49
Character
  • A State of Character is a set of
  • 1. Habits,
  • 2. Passion,
  • 3. Pleasure,
  • 4. Thoughts,
  • 5. the like.
  • Thus to say that virtue is a a state of
    character is to say that a virtuous person not
    only reliably performs virtuous acts but also
    feels the right passions, desires the right
    objects, enjoys the right things, and holds the
    right beliefs in the each situation.
  • Consider the following example

50
Character
  • A courageous person will not only stand firm in
    battle but will also feel the right amoun of fear
    and confidence and have the right goals. He will
    not be thinking, I cant run because I am so
    terrified that my legs are off-line, and besides
    if I stand firm, I may get to appear on CNN.
    Instead, he will be thinking, The situation is
    perilous, but I have a reasonable chance of
    surviving if I keep alert, and besides I must
    stand firm to keep my city free. It is the brave
    thing to do.

51
Character
  • Is Aristotle demanding an unreasonably high
    level of perfection from his virtuous person?
  • 1. Virtue is a matter of degree and Aristotle is
    sketching a perfect virtue. He is describing
    an ideal person so that we can have a mark at
    which to aim and a standard for judgment.
  • 2. A person can be reasonably less than ideal
    and still be a virtuous person.
  • The bottom line is that your passions and
    desires are under your control. To be sure, you
    cant change them quickly or easily, but over
    time you can modify your passions and desires.
    In fact, Aristotle says that you should use your
    reason to determine which passions and desires to
    have and then go on to develop these passions and
    desires. You should cultivate a taste for
    virtue, just as some people cultivate a taste for
    gourmet coffee (1113a-1114b).

52
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • Aristotle describes ethical virtue as a hexis
    (state condition disposition)a tendency or
    disposition, induced by our habits, to have
    appropriate feelings (1105b25-6).
  • Defective states of character are hexeis (plural
    of hexis) as well, but they are tendencies to
    have inappropriate feelings.
  • The significance of Aristotle's characterization
    of these states as hexeis is his decisive
    rejection of the thesis, found throughout Plato's
    early dialogues, that virtue is nothing but a
    kind of knowledge and vice nothing but a lack of
    knowledge.
  • Although Aristotle frequently draws analogies
    between the crafts and the virtues (and similarly
    between physical health and eudaimonia), he
    insists that the virtues differ from the crafts
    and all branches of knowledge in that the former
    involve appropriate emotional responses and are
    not purely intellectual conditions.

53
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • Every ethical virtue is a condition intermediate
    between two other states, one involving excess,
    and the other deficiency (1106a26-b28).
  • 1. Virtues are no different from technical
    skills every skilled worker knows how to avoid
    excess and deficiency, and is in a condition
    intermediate between two extremes.
  • 2. For example, the courageous person, for
    example, judges that some dangers are worth
    facing and others not, and experiences fear to a
    degree that is appropriate to his circumstances.
    He lies between the coward, who flees every
    danger and experiences excessive fear, and the
    rash person, who judges every danger worth
    facing and experiences little or no fear.

54
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • 2. Aristotle holds that this same topography
    applies to every ethical virtue all are
    located on a map that places the virtues between
    states of excess and deficiency.
  • 3. The mean is to be determined in a way that
    takes into account the particular circumstances
    of the individual (1106a36-b7).
  • Example The arithmetic mean between 10 and 2
    is 6, and this is so invariably, whatever is
    being counted. But the intermediate point that
    is chosen by an expert in any of the crafts will
    vary from one situation to another. There is no
    universal rule, for example, about how much food
    an athlete should eat, and it would be absurd to
    infer from the fact that 10 lbs. is too much and
    2 lbs. too little for me that I should eat 6
    lbs. Finding the mean in any given situation is
    not a mechanical or thoughtless procedure, but
    requires a full and detailed acquaintance with
    the circumstances

55
Virtue (courage)
People
Degree
Vice (cowardice)
Duration
Vice (Rashness)
Objects
Occasions
Brutish
56
A Character Trait is a Virtue IFF it is conducive
to eudaimonia
Virtue Excess
Deficiency Sphere
Courage Rashness Cowardice Danger Temperance S
elf-indulgence Insensibility Sensual
pleasure Liberality Wasteful Stinginess Money M
agnificence Vulgarity Penny pinching Great
wealth Pride Vanity Humility Honor
self-respect Right Ambition Overly
ambitious Lack of ambition Honor Good temper No
emotion Quick-temper Insult Ready
wit Buffoonishness Boorishness Humor Truthfulness
Boastfulness Modesty Self-description Friendlin
ess Flattery Quarrelsome Social
association Shame Bashfulness Pretense Wrongdoi
ng Righteous Spite Envy Fortune of
others Justice Greed ? Scarce goods
57
How does Aristotle Know which Traits are Virtues?
  • It is not by uncritical adoption of values of his
    time for Aristotle is quite critical of certain
    institutions within society (e.g., slavery) is
    willing to state that certain traits are
    virtues/vices even though they have not been
    previously been identified as such by his
    society.
  • Aristotle says that a character trait is a virtue
    IFF it is conducive to leading the happy life
    (eudaimonia).

58
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • It should be evident that Aristotle's treatment
    of virtues as mean states endorses the idea that
    we should sometimes have strong feelingswhen
    such feelings are called for by our situation.
    Sometimes only a small degree of anger is
    appropriate but at other times, circumstances
    call for great anger. The right amount is not
    some quantity between zero and the highest
    possible level, but rather the amount, whatever
    it happens to be, that is proportionate to the
    seriousness of the situation. Of course,
    Aristotle is committed to saying that anger
    should never reach the point at which it
    undermines reason and this means that our
    passion should always fall short of the extreme
    point at which we would lose control. But it is
    possible to be very angry without going to this
    extreme, and Aristotle does not intend to deny
    this.

59
2 Distinct Theories Regarding the Doctrine of the
Mean
  • 1st There is the thesis that every virtue is a
    state that lies between two vices, one of excess
    and the other of deficiency.
  • 2nd There is the idea that whenever a virtuous
    person chooses to perform a virtuous act, he
    can be described as aiming at an act that is in
    some way or other intermediate between
    alternatives that he rejects. I
  • Second is more objectionable. A critic might
    concede that in some cases virtuous acts can be
    described in Aristotle's terms. If, for example,
    one is trying to decide how much to spend on a
    wedding present, one is looking for an amount
    that is neither excessive nor deficient. But
    surely many other problems that confront a
    virtuous agent are not susceptible to this
    quantitative analysis. If one must decide whether
    to attend a wedding or respect a competing
    obligation instead, it would not be illuminating
    to describe this as a search for a mean between
    extremesunless aiming at the mean simply
    becomes another phrase for trying to make the
    right decision. The objection, then, is that
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean, taken as a
    doctrine about what the ethical agent does when
    he deliberates, is in many cases inapplicable or
    unilluminating.

60
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • A defense of Aristotle would have to say that the
    virtuous person does after all aim at a mean, if
    we allow for a broad enough notion of what sort
    of aiming is involved. For example, consider a
    juror who must determine whether a defendant is
    guilty as charged. He does not have before his
    mind a quantitative question he is trying to
    decide whether the accused committed the crime,
    and is not looking for some quantity of action
    intermediate between extremes. Nonetheless, an
    excellent juror can be described as someone who,
    in trying to arrive at the correct decision,
    seeks to express the right degree of concern for
    all relevant considerations. He searches for the
    verdict that results from a deliberative process
    that is neither overly credulous or unduly
    skeptical. Similarly, in facing situations that
    arouse anger, a virtuous agent must determine
    what action (if any) to take in response to an
    insult, and although this is not itself a
    quantitative question, his attempt to answer it
    properly requires him to have the right degree of
    concern for his standing as a member of the
    community. He aims at a mean in the sense that he
    looks for a response that avoids too much or too
    little attention to factors that must be taken
    into account in making a wise decision.

61
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • Perhaps a greater difficulty can be raised if we
    ask how Aristotle determines which emotions are
    governed by the doctrine of the mean. Consider
    someone who loves to wrestle, for example. Is
    this passion something that must be felt by every
    human being at appropriate times and to the right
    degree? Surely someone who never felt this
    emotion to any degree could still live a
    perfectly happy life. Why then should we not say
    the same about at least some of the emotions that
    Aristotle builds into his analysis of the
    ethically virtuous agent? Why should we
    experience anger at all, or fear, or the degree
    of concern for wealth and honor that Aristotle
    commends? These are precisely the questions that
    were asked in antiquity by the Stoics, and they
    came to the conclusion that such common emotions
    as anger and fear are always inappropriate.
    Aristotle assumes, on the contrary, not simply
    that these common passions are sometimes
    appropriate, but that it is essential that every
    human being learn how to master them and
    experience them in the right way at the right
    times. A defense of his position would have to
    show that the emotions that figure in his account
    of the virtues are valuable components of any
    well-lived human life, when they are experienced
    properly. Perhaps such a project could be carried
    out, but Aristotle himself does not attempt to do
    so.

62
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • He often says, in the course of his discussion,
    that when the good person chooses to act
    virtuously, he does so for the sake of the
    kalona word that can mean beautiful,
    noble, or fine. (See for example 1120a23-4.)
    This term indicates that Aristotle sees in
    ethical activity an attraction that is comparable
    to the beauty of well-crafted artifacts,
    including such artifacts as poetry, music, and
    drama. He draws this analogy in his discussion of
    the mean, when he says that every craft tries to
    produce a work from which nothing should be taken
    away and to which nothing further should be added
    (1106b5-14). A craft product, when well designed
    and produced by a good craftsman, is not merely
    useful, but also has such elements as balance,
    proportion and harmonyfor these are properties
    that help make it useful. Similarly, Aristotle
    holds that a well-executed project that expresses
    the ethical virtues will not merely be
    advantageous but kalon as wellfor the balance it
    strikes is part of what makes it advantageous.
    The young person learning to acquire the virtues
    must develop a love of doing what is kalon and a
    strong aversion to its oppositethe aischron, the
    shameful and ugly. Determining what is kalon is
    difficult (1106b28-33, 1109a24-30, and the normal
    human aversion to embracing difficulties helps
    account for the scarcity of virtue (1104b10-11).

63
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • It should be clear that neither the thesis that
    virtues lie between extremes nor the thesis that
    the good person aims at what is intermediate is
    intended as a procedure for making decisions.
    These doctrines of the mean help show what is
    attractive about the virtues, and they also help
    systematize our understanding of which qualities
    are virtues. Once we see that temperance,
    courage, and other generally recognized
    characteristics are mean states, we are in a
    position to generalize and to identify other mean
    states as virtues, even though they are not
    qualities for which we have a name. Aristotle
    remarks, for example, that the mean state with
    respect to anger has no name in Greek
    (1125b26-7). Though he is guided to some degree
    by distinctions captured by ordinary terms, his
    methodology allows him to recognize states for
    which no names exist.

64
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • So far from offering a decision procedure,
    Aristotle insists that this is something that no
    ethical theory can do. His theory elucidates the
    nature of virtue, but what must be done on any
    particular occasion by a virtuous agent depends
    on the circumstances, and these vary so much from
    one occasion to another that there is no
    possibility of stating a series of rules, however
    complicated, that collectively solve every
    practical problem. This feature of ethical theory
    is not unique Aristotle thinks it applies to
    many crafts, such as medicine and navigation
    (1104a7-10). He says that the virtuous person
    sees the truth in each case, being as it were a
    standard and measure of them (1113a32-3) but
    this appeal to the good person's vision should
    not be taken to mean that he has an inarticulate
    and incommunicable insight into the truth.

65
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • Aristotle thinks of the good person as someone
    who is good at deliberation, and he describes
    deliberation as a process of rational inquiry.
    The intermediate point that the good person tries
    to find is determined by logos (reason,
    account) and in the way that the person of
    practical reason would determine it (1107a1-2).
    To say that such a person sees what to do is
    simply a way of registering the point that the
    good person's reasoning does succeed in
    discovering what is best in each situation. He is
    as it were a standard and measure in the sense
    that his views should be regarded as
    authoritative by other members of the community.
    A standard or measure is something that settles
    disputes and because good people are so skilled
    at discovering the mean in difficult cases, their
    advice must be sought and heeded.

66
Relationship between Virtue and Vice
  • Although there is no possibility of writing a
    book of rules, however long, that will serve as a
    complete guide to wise decision-making, it would
    be a mistake to attribute to Aristotle the
    opposite position, namely that every purported
    rule admits of exceptions, so that even a small
    rule-book that applies to a limited number of
    situations is an impossibility. He makes it clear
    that certain emotions (spite, shamelessness,
    envy) and actions (adultery, theft, murder) are
    always wrong, regardless of the circumstances
    (1107a8-12). Although he says that the names of
    these emotions and actions convey their
    wrongness, he should not be taken to mean that
    their wrongness derives from linguistic usage. He
    defends the family as a social institution
    against the criticisms of Plato (Politics
    II.3-4), and so when he says that adultery is
    always wrong, he is prepared to argue for his
    point by explaining why marriage is a valuable
    custom and why extra-marital intercourse
    undermines the relationship between husband and
    wife. He is not making the tautological claim
    that wrongful sexual activity is wrong, but the
    more specific and contentious point that
    marriages ought to be governed by a rule of
    strict fidelity. Similarly, when he says that
    murder and theft are always wrong, he does not
    mean that wrongful killing and taking are wrong,
    but that the current system of laws regarding
    these matters ought to be strictly enforced. So,
    although Aristotle holds that ethics cannot be
    reduced to a system of rules, however complex, he
    insists that some rules are inviolable.

67
Aristotles Starting Point
  • We have seen that the decisions of a practically
    wise person are not mere intuitions, but can be
    justified by a chain of reasoning. (This is why
    Aristotle often talks in term of a practical
    syllogism, with a major premise that identifies
    some good to be achieved, and a minor premise
    that locates the good in some present-to-hand
    situation.) At the same time, he is acutely aware
    of the fact that reasoning can always be traced
    back to a starting point that is not itself
    justified by further reasoning. Neither good
    theoretical reasoning nor good practical
    reasoning moves in a circle true thinking always
    presupposes and progresses in linear fashion from
    proper starting points. And that leads him to ask
    for an account of how the proper starting points
    of reasoning are to be determined. Practical
    reasoning always presupposes that one has some
    end, some goal one is trying to achieve and the
    task of reasoning is determine how that goal is
    to be accomplished. (This need not be means-end
    reasoning in the conventional sense if, for
    example, our goal is the just resolution of a
    conflict, we must determine what constitutes
    justice in these particular circumstances. Here
    we are engaged in ethical inquiry, and are not
    asking a purely instrumental question.) But if
    practical reasoning is correct only if it begins
    from a correct premise, what is it that insures
    the correctness of its starting point?

68
Aristotles Starting Point
  • Aristotle replies Virtue makes the goal right,
    practical wisdom the things leading to it
    (1144a7-8). By this he cannot mean that there is
    no room for reasoning about our ultimate end. For
    as we have seen, he gives a reasoned defense of
    his conception of happiness as virtuous activity.
    What he must have in mind, when he says that
    virtue makes the goal right, is that deliberation
    typically proceeds from a goal that is far more
    specific than the goal of attaining happiness by
    acting virtuously. To be sure, there may be
    occasions when a good person approaches an
    ethical problem by beginning with the premise
    that happiness consists in virtuous activity. But
    more often what happens is that a concrete goal
    presents itself as his starting pointhelping a
    friend in need, or supporting a worthwhile civic
    project. Which specific project we set for
    ourselves is determined by our character. A good
    person starts from worthwhile concrete ends
    because his habits and emotional orientation have
    given him the ability to recognize that such
    goals are within reach, here and now. Those who
    are defective in character may have the rational
    skill needed to achieve their endsthe skill
    Aristotle calls cleverness (1144a23-8)but often
    the ends they seek are worthless. The cause of
    this deficiency lies not in some impairment in
    their capacity to reasonfor we are assuming that
    they are normal in this respectbut in the
    training of their passions.

69
  • Nicomachean Ethics was written not in order to
    know what virtue is, but in order to become
    good.
  • The choices and actions will be free of the
    conflict pain that inevitably accompanies the
    aktratic and enkratic agent. This is because the
    part of the soul that governs choice and action
    is so disposed that desire and right judgment
    coincide. Thus, acquiring a stable disposition
    (hexis) of this sort amounts to acquiring moral
    virtue (ethike arete). This disposition is
    concerned with choices as would be determined by
    the person of practical wisdom (phronesis) these
    will be actions lying between extreme
    alternatives.

70
  • In the virtuous person, desire and judgment agree
    whereby the choices and actions will be free of
    the conflict and pain that inevitably accompany
    those who are akratic and/or enkratic

The enkratic The enkratic is the morally strong
person who shares the akratic agents desire to
do other than what he knows ought to be done,
but acts in accordance with his better judgment.
The akratic The akratic is the morally weak
person who desires to do other than what he knows
ought to be done and acts on this desire against
his better judgment.
In neither kind of choice are desire and judgment
in harmony. In the virtuous desire and judgment
agree.
71
Why does desire and judgment agree for the
virtuous?
  • The reason why the choices and actions will be
    free of the conflict and pain that inevitably
    accompanies those of the akratic and enkratic
    agent is because the part of their soul that
    governs choice and action is so disposed that
    desire and judgment coincide. The disposition is
    concerned with choices as would be determined by
    the person of practical wisdom (phronesis) these
    will be actions lying between extreme
    alternatives. They will lie in a man-popularly
    called the golden mean-relative to the talents
    and stores of the agent.

72
Why does desire and judgment agree for the
virtuous?
  • Choosing in this way is not easily done. It
    involves, for instance, feeling anger or
    extending generosity at the right time, toward
    the right people, in the right way, and for the
    right reasons. Intellectual virtues, such as
    excellence at mathematics, can be acquired by
    teaching, but moral virtues cannot. I may know
    what ought to be done and even perform virtuous
    act without being able to act virtuously.
    Nonetheless, because moral virtue is a
    disposition concerning choice, deliberate
    performance of virtuous acts can, ultimately,
    instill a disposition to choose them in harmony
    and with pleasure, and hence, to act virtuously.

73
What does it take to be fully virtuous?
  • The fully virtuous do what they should without a
    struggle against contrary desire possess
    practical wisdom (phronesis) which is the
    knowledge or understanding that enables its
    possessor to do just that in any given situation.
    Most contend that phronesis comes out of at
    least two sources
  • 1. Comes only with the experience of life. The
    virtuous are mindful of the consequences of
    possible actions. How could they fail to be
    reckless, thoughtless and short-sighted if they
    were not?
  • 2. They have the capacit
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com