When Compositionality Fails to Predict Systematicity - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

When Compositionality Fails to Predict Systematicity

Description:

With a few syllables it can express an incalculable number of thoughts, so that ... between red apple (red on the outside) and pink grapefruit (pink on the inside) ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:29
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 33
Provided by: orensc1
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: When Compositionality Fails to Predict Systematicity


1
When Compositionality Fails to Predict
Systematicity
  • Reinhard Blutner, Petra Hendriks,
  • Helen de Hoop, Oren Schwartz

2
The immediate appeal of compositionality Frege
(1923)
  • It is astonishing what language can do. With a
    few syllables it can express an incalculable
    number of thoughts, so that even a thought
    grasped by a terrestrial being for the first time
    can be put into a form of words which will be
    understood by
  • someone to whom the thought is entirely new. This
    would be impossible, were we not able to
    distinguish parts in the thoughts corresponding
    to the parts of a sentence, so that the structure
    of the sentence serves as the image of the
    structure of the thoughts.

3
Compositionality
  • The meaning of a complex expression is
    determined by its structure and the meanings of
    its constitutents.
  • equivalently
  • There is a homomorphism between the syntactic
    term algebra to the algebra of meanings.

4
Compositionality
  • Compositionality is necessary to explain the
    productivity of language.
  • Compositionality entails productivity.

5
Systematicity
  • The term and empirical hypothesis was introduced
    by Fodor Pylyshyn (1988), who didnt attempt a
    precise definition of the concept or a complete
    description of the empirical phenomenon.
  • Van Gelder Niklasson (1994) summarize FPs
    notion of systematicity as the ability to do
    some things of a given cognitive type (including
    at least thinking a thought and making an
    inference) is intrinsically connected with their
    ability to do other, structurally related things
    of that type.

6
Systematicity
  • When an agent understands the expressions brown
    triangle and black square, she understands the
    expressions brown square and black triangle as
    well.

Does compositionality entail systematicity?
7
A Classical Example
  • Agent understands brown triangle and black
    square.
  • She constructs the conceptual representations
    BROWN?TRIANGLE and BLACK?SQUARE (via
    compositionality).
  • She knows the truth conditional impact of the
    corresponding constitutents, and she extracts the
    lexicon entries brown -gt BROWN, square-gtSQUARE,
    etc.
  • Using these, she constructs BROWN?SQUARE and
    BLACK?TRIANGLE (via compositionality)
  • Thus compositionality may derive systematicity

8
Systematicity
  • If an agent understands
  • within an hour and without a watch,
  • does she also understand
  • within a watch and without an hour?
  • (Szabo 2004)

9
Our View
  • Language is (mostly) systematic and
    compositional, but not always.
  • Traditional semantic analyses have difficulty
    with cases where the systematicity of meaning is
    weak or missing.
  • Connectionist models are well suited to handling
    these types of cases, and can account for the
    semantic contribution of a constitutent that is
    both systematic (in general) and idiosyncratic
    (in certain cases).

10
Why compositionality fails to explain
systsematicity
  • In his Grundlagen der Mathematik Frege (1884)
    noticed the context-dependence of words (and took
    this as an argument against compositionality in
    NL)
  • One should ask for the meaning of a word only
    in the context of a sentence, and not in
    isolation.

11
Empirical Phenomena
  • Quine (1960) was the first who noted the contrast
    between red apple (red on the outside) and pink
    grapefruit (pink on the inside).
  • Lahav (1993) argues that an adjective such as
    brown doesnt make a simple and fixed
    contribution to any composite expression in which
    it appears
  • brown cow, brown crystal, brown book, brown
    newspaper

12
Empirical Phenomena
  • Different colors typically denoted by red in red
    apple and red hair.
  • the actual color value deviates in a systematic
    way from the prototypical color value that can be
    assigned to the color adjective in isolation in
    dependency on the conceptual properties of the
    modified noun
  • Similarly, the same color is often described with
    different adjectives
  • In Japanese, brown sugar, aka-zatoo (lit. red
    sugar) comes in the same range of colors as
    shira-miso, (lit. white bean paste)

13
Three consequences
  • Intersectivity, A(B) A(x)?B,
    doesnt hold, even for most absolute adjectives
  • Systematicity statements cannot be derived from
    compositionality in these cases
  • Encyclopedic knowledge is required to determine
    the truth conditional content of an utterance
    (explicature in Relevance Theory).

14
A Related Phenomenon
  • Typicality
  • A specific instance of a red apple is more
    typical of a red apple than of an apple
  • Incompatible Conjunctions
  • The typicality effects are greater for
    incompatible conjunctions (striped apple) than
    for compatible conjunctions (green apple)

15
A Concrete Question
  • How should we account for the semantic
    contribution of an (absolute) adjective to an
    (Adjective Noun)N complex expression in the face
    of these phenomena?

16
Radical underspecificationwith contextual
enrichment
  • small ? ?x small(x,N)
  • small terrier ? ?x small(x,N) terrier(x)
  • Analogously for red apple with place-holders for
    the relevant parts
  • red ? ?x part(Y,x) red(Y)
  • red apple ??x part(Y,x) red(Y) apple(x)
  • How to determine the proper values for N and Y,
    respectively?
  • Contextual enrichment, as in Probabilistic Theory
    of Relevance (van Rooy 2000)
  • with small(x,N) ? size(x) lt N

17
Problems with underspecification
  • Does not really clarify how to determine the
    border line between the underspecified
    representation and the contextual enrichment
  • It is difficult to see how the available
    mechanisms account for the prototype effects
    found in adjectival modification

18
A connectionist approach
  • Inspired by the (symbolic)
  • selective modification model
  • (Smith, Osherson, Rips Keane 1988)
  • Prototype representations consisting of
  • Symbolic, structured concepts
  • Attribute-value pairs, weighted by salience
  • Modifiers act on prototypes by increasing
    salience of attribute and changing its value
  • Tverskys (1977) contrast rule for similarity

19
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
20
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
Color
21
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
Taste
22
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
Peel
23
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Pulp
Conceptual Layer
24
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
(Color x Peel)
Conceptual Layer
Peel
Color
25
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
red
26
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
white
27
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
white pulp
red peel
Conceptual Layer
red
28
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
29
A connectionist approach
Adjective
Noun
Conceptual Layer
30
A connectinist approach
  • Default uniform connections within conceptual
    layer
  • In training, instances are presented at the
    conceptual layer and at the (localist) adjective
    and noun layers.
  • The prototypes learned by the model are found by
    turning on units in the adjective and noun layers
    and letting the network settle into a
    representation at the conceptual layer.

31
Prototype effects
  • Using Tversky's (1977) contrast rule (formulated
    for activation vectors) sim(s,t) ??i
    min(si,ti) ? ??i si ?ti
  • sim(sred apple, t1) gt sim(sapple, t1)
  • sim(spurple apple,t2)?sim(sapple,t2)
  • gt sim(sred apple,t1)?sim(sapple,t1)
  • t1 a red apple, t2 a purple apple

32
Conclusions
  • Compositionality alone is not formally
    restrictive enough to explain the type of
    productivity in NL
  • Semantic contributions of constituents to their
    complex expressions are more complex and less
    systematic than we might expect
  • Encyclopedic knowledge is necessary to account
    for the variability in the semantic contribution
    of constituents to complex phrases
  • Connectionist approaches easily handle the
    accumulation and application of this knowledge.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com