Common Mistakes in Thinking - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 39
About This Presentation
Title:

Common Mistakes in Thinking

Description:

Informal fallacy An error in reasoning resulting from ... Cindy Crawford always drinks Pepsi. If I drink a lot of Pepsi, I might look like Cindy Crawford. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:124
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 40
Provided by: jenn277
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Common Mistakes in Thinking


1
Common Mistakes in Thinking
  • Informal fallacy An error in reasoning
    resulting from carelessness, inattention, or
    insensitivity to language or context in which the
    argument is presented. In many instances of
    informal fallacies, we are tempted to accept the
    argument because we are not attentive enough to
    recognize that the evidential structure is
    unacceptable as presented.
  • Informal fallacies are the most common kind of
    mistake in arguments. They can be hard to avoid
    or to detect precisely because they are so
    common. They are the main traps to avoid in
    arguments and scrupulously avoid in our own.

2
Ad hominem
  • The first informal fallacy is the argument to the
    person. The Latin name, argumentum ad hominem,
    is probably the most commonly used of the Latin
    words in logic, and sometimes it appears simply
    as ad hominem. In this fallacy an attack is made
    on the person presenting the argument rather than
    on the argument itself. The character,
    credentials, reputation, position, or office of
    the individual is called into question instead of
    the soundness of his o her claim. The person is
    made to seem ridiculous or suspicious, and this
    is meant to undermine the argument that is
    presented.

3
Ad hominem II
  • The ad hominem fallacy actually has two versions,
    personal and circumstantial. In the personal
    form (which is the most common one), the
    character or behavior of the person is
    discredited. Ad hominem almost always results
    from saying, in effect,
  • So and sos claim should be rejected because
    so-and-so is ____________, where nearly any term
    with presumably negative impact is placed in the
    blank (for example, ignorant, a liar, a
    Republican, a Democrat, just saying that to
    get rich, and so on).
  • Rare exceptions can occur in which a persons
    shortcomings do automatically transfer to the
    persons claim, but such a transaction takes a
    peculiar kind of circumstance. For example, He
    was paid to lie about this matter.

4
Ad hominem III
  • In the 19th century the fight for Irish home rule
    was criticized because its leader, Charles
    Parnell, was an adulterer. Vincent Van Gogh
    suffered from severe depression, but that does
    not have any bearing on the aesthetic value of
    his paintings.
  • The point is that in judging ideas one mustnt
    judge the person presenting the ideas. Insane
    people can write profound things, the sane can
    produce a lot of nonsense awful people can say
    good things, and saints may not be right in
    everything they argue.

5
Ad hominem IV
  • In the circumstantial form of ad hominem, the
    persons position is cited as the reason to
    disregard what he or she claims. Example
  • John says that we should reject what Father
    Hennesy says about the dangers of abortion
    because, After all, hes a Catholic priest, and
    priests are required to hold such views.
  • It may be true that Father Hennesy is a priest
    and that is views on abortion represent those of
    the Catholic church. That does not make his
    views false, however. The specific mistake here,
    of course, is to presuppose that people always
    act for their own advantage and because of their
    position, and that does not seem fair.

6
Ad hominem V
  • Ad hominem is Latin for to the man indicating
    that it is the person and not the subject matter
    thats being addressed.
  • Rather than arguments ad hominem, we must use
    arguments ad rem, that is, to the thing itself.
  • A variety of the fallacy of ad hominem
    circumstantial is called tu quoque or you
    yourself. Here an argument is discredited
    because the person does not practice what she
    preaches. For example, You tell me not to smoke
    but you do. Of course, if someone is seriously
    against smoking than they should not smoke.
    However, their judgment is not invalidated by the
    personal inconsistency.

7
Ad hominem VI
  • This does not mean, of course, that questions
    about a persons behavior or position are always
    beside the point. If we want to know if
    candidates are fit for office, their character
    traits are certainly relevant. Such virtues as
    sincerity, fairness, integrity, and so forth are
    important considerations. However, we call it
    smear tactics when irrelevant facts about a
    persons political position or qualifications for
    public office. The fact that a woman may be
    divorced or a lesbian, for example, does not seem
    relevant to whether she would make a good
    legislator.

8
Ad hominem VII
  • The argument to the person has its counterpart in
    the biographical fallacy in literature. Knowing
    that Virginia Woolf suffered from depression may
    help us interpret some of her work, but knowing
    her life has no bearing on the literary value of
    her novels.
  • In other academic fields the same mistake is
    termed the genetic fallacy, and it refers to the
    attempt to explain away a claim by referring to
    the source.

9
Ad hominem VIII
  • In religion, William James refers to the fallacy
    as medical materialism
  • Perhaps the commonest expression of this
    assumptionis seen in those comments in which
    unsentimental people so often pass on their more
    sentimental acquaintances. Alfred believes in
    immortality so strongly because his temperament
    is so emotional. Fannys extraordinary
    conscientiousness is merely a matter of
    overinstigated nerves. Williams melancholy
    about the universe is due to bad
    digestion-probably his liver is torpid. Elizas
    delight in her church is a symptom of her
    hysterical constitution. Peter would be less
    troubled with his soul if he would take more
    exercise in the open air, etc. William James,
    Varieties of Religious Experience
  • The source of an idea is irrelevant to its truth.

10
Argument from authority
  • The argument from authority fallacy is committed
    whenever we argue for some point, not because it
    is well grounded in fact or logic but because of
    the authority of the person who presented it.
    The standing or prestige of a recognized
    authority is said to guarantee the truth of a
    claim, and anyone who doubts it is made to feel
    presumptuous or egotistical. The thrust of the
    argument is Who are you to challenge the
    judgment of this authority or the experience of
    that expert?

11
Argument from authority II
  • In some ways this fallacy is the mirror image of
    the argument to the person. Rather than
    dismissing a position because of the person who
    advocates it, in the argument from authority one
    accepts a position because of the person
    advocating it. Here too the messenger is
    confused with the message. Example
  • Of course different people have different
    strengths. But Aristotles definition of
    personhood emphasized rationality, so the ability
    to reason is the only personal characteristic
    that really matters.
  • Cindy Crawford always drinks Pepsi. If I drink a
    lot of Pepsi, I might look like Cindy Crawford.

12
Argument from authority III
  • No one can check the evidence for everything that
    is claimed, so we must depend on the information
    provided by authorities. However, and idea does
    not become true simply because an authority says
    so the person must have a good reason to say so.
  • If we accept people as authorities it is because
    we have confidence that they support their
    insights with good thinking and good evidence.
    Furthermore, the evidence should be publicly
    verifiable, whether in the form of reproducible
    experiments or rational reasons that anyone can
    consider.

13
Argument from authority III
  • A wider problem with the argument from authority
    is it suggests that an authority in one field is
    also an in another. We make this mistake very
    often in the fields of sports and entertainment.
    For instance, outstanding baseball players might
    be trusted to recommend athletic equipment but
    they are authority not qualified to endorse
    camcorders or razors in TV commercials. In the
    same way, actors are knowledgeable about acting
    but not necessarily about long distance telephone
    service, cruise lines, refrigerators, or cars.
    An ethical problem with such endorsements, of
    course is that the celebrities may not actually
    use the product they recommend but are mainly
    interested in the large endorsement fees.

14
Argument from Force
  • Another informal fallacy is called the argument
    from force. This fallacy substitutes an appeal to
    motive in place of evidence in the grounds
    supporting a claim. In the appeal to force,
    someone attempts to get you to accept her claim
    because she somehow will hurt you if you do not
    agree. Example
  • Your supervisor at work asks you to support her
    request for a merit raise. By all accounts,
    including your personal observation of her
    performance, she has done a thoroughly miserable
    job and does not deserve merit recognition in her
    salary. However, she makes it clear that your
    job is on the line if you do not support her. So
    you write the letter supporting her request.

15
Argument from Force II
  • Arguments from force amounts to holding a gun to
    someones head and saying, I trust you will see
    the force of my argument. This device can be
    convincing, and it may ultimately prevail, but
    not because it has satisfied logical standards.
    Al Capone once remarked, You can get more with a
    kind word and a gun than you can with a kind
    word. Of course, it depends on what you are
    trying to get. You have not converted a man
    because you have silenced him. John Morley
  • One may get temporary obedience through appeal to
    force but lose trust, respect, love, honest
    loyalty, and so forth.

16
Argument from Force II
  • In the argument from force the intimidation
    sometimes will be overt and physical, as when
    citizens are compelled to vote for a dictator
    upon pain of death. However, usually the
    intimidation is more subtle and indirect. For
    example, if the boss strongly suggests that an
    employee agree that the safety standards are
    adequate, or that an accounting report is
    accurate, the boss is probably making an argument
    from force. The employee will feel that he or
    she had better go along, not blow the whistle, or
    else the job will go to someone who can rise
    above principles.

17
Argument from Force II
  • In religious discussions people will sometimes
    say There are no atheists in foxholes, implying
    that we will always turn to religion in times of
    crisis. Even if that is true, fear is not an
    argument for Gods existence. The most famous
    example of the argument from force within
    religion is Pascals Wager.
  • Pascal was a seventeenth century scientist and
    philosopher. He argued that if we believe in God
    and we are right, then we will go to heaven and
    if we believe in God and we are wrong then at
    least we will have a pleasant life on earth
    thinking that God exists and we will ultimately
    receive our heavenly reward. On the other hand,
    if we do not believe in God and we are wrong,
    then we will surely burn in hell and if we do
    not believe in God and we are right, then we will
    have a miserable life on earth, feeling that no
    divine mercy, justice or love exists.

18
Argument from Force II
  • Since these are the only options, Pascal argued,
    we should certainly bet on belief in God because,
    right or wrong, we are far better off. If we
    wager on not believing then, right or wrong, we
    are bound to suffer. In essence, Pascal is
    arguing that if we know whats good for us we had
    better believe in God. Clearly the argument is
    meant to intimidate us into accepting Gods
    existence in this respect it functions as an
    argument from force. No proof is offered that
    there is a God, but only that we ought to believe
    in God to be on the safe side. However, to
    believe that something is real we need good
    reasons, not just the fear that we might be sorry
    if we didnt.

19
Appeal to pity
  • Appeal to pity is a fallacy that is committed
    whenever the evidential appeal is only to the
    altruistic ideals of the hearer. Example
  • Helen is running for a seat on the city council.
    Though you like her, you have doubts about her
    qualifications and in fact believe that an
    opposing candidate would make a better member of
    the council. When you communicate your concerns
    about her qualifications to a mutual friend, the
    friend counters by saying that Helen would be
    terribly hurt if she were to lose the election.
    After thinking this over, you conclude that maybe
    Helens qualifications are not so bad after all.

20
Appeal to pity II
  • The mutual friend has evoked compassion in you
    for Helen, but she has not given you a reason for
    changing your opinion of Helens qualifications.
    Does your compassion for Helen enter the picture
    at all? Certainly, but only in this way You now
    have to weigh Helens hurt at losing the election
    against the consequences of having her as a
    council member instead of the BETTER QUALIFIED
    candidate. Which, you have to decide, is more
    important?

21
Appeal to pity II
  • As a student you may have used the argument from
    pity at one time or another. You may have asked
    for a higher grade on an exam, arguing that you
    had studied hard but were emotionally upset or
    swamped with work. You might have said that you
    have a twenty hour a week job, your car broke
    down, you were sick with the flu, or that you are
    having trouble with your parents. Under such
    circumstances, a sympathetic professor might
    allow you additional time to do the work or even
    let you retake the exam, but if the professor
    were to raise your grade on those grounds he or
    she would not be acting in a professional way.

22
Appeal to pity III
  • A higher grade would indicate that you had
    mastered the material to a greater degree than
    you actually did, thereby giving a false
    impression to anyone reading your transcript.
    Your grade should reflect your actual level of
    achievement, not how much sympathy the professor
    felt for you.
  • Imagine being operated on by a doctor who never
    really mastered the skills of surgery but was
    given a passing grade by the professor how
    thought he or she deserved a break. Imagine
    driving over bridges that were designed by
    engineers who were allowed to graduate, not
    because they had met the qualifications, but
    because they had worked hard and came from poor
    families.

23
Appeal to pity IV
  • Lets look at another example
  • ROOFER Im positive that my work will meet your
    requirements. I really need the money, what with
    my wife being sick an all.
  • The roofer seems to be giving a reason for
    thinking that his work will meet your
    requirements. But of course he is not that
    issue is unaffected by the fact that he really
    needs the money. This fact is not a reason, not
    even a bad reason, for concluding anything at all
    about the quality of his work.

24
Appeal to pity V
  • Notice, though, that actions performed out of
    concern for others are often rationally and
    ethically justified. Indeed, in some instances
    they are among the noblest of human deeds. If
    the roofer is qualified and needs the money for
    his wifes illness, and you are willing to take a
    chance on him then by all means hire him! Just
    dont think that he has given you a reason for
    thinking that his work will meet your
    specifications whether it will or not is
    something you must establish on other grounds.

25
Straw Person
  • Another fallacy is called straw person, the
    mistake of attributing to your opponents a
    ridiculous position that they do not hold and
    that is easily knocked down like a person made of
    straw. By exaggerating, oversimplifying, or
    distorting the other persons views, you set up
    an easy target. This absurd position, not the
    persons actual one, is then refuted by showing
    how ludicrous it is.
  • The straw person device is frequently used in
    political rhetoric, functioning as a cheap way of
    winning points while evading the main issue.

26
Straw Person II
  • For example, a politician might argue,
  • My liberal, environmentalist friend believes in
    preserving species, that the spotted owl and the
    snail darter are more important than people. Im
    sorry, but I cannot share that view. He would
    not sacrifice a bird or a fish to safeguard a
    human being, but I would rather let an animal die
    than a person.
  • Quite obviously, few if any environmentalists
    would claim that the life of a bird or fish has a
    higher value than that of a human being, but the
    environmentalists position is cast in that light
    to make it easy to refute. The environmental
    debate is not over whether we should kill people
    rather than animals but the extent to which we
    should endanger wildlife for the sake of economic
    development.

27
Straw Person III
  • That, of course, is a genuine question that
    deserves to be discussed and debated. Should the
    protection of an endangered species prevent the
    development of our natural resources, especially
    if that development means increased employment,
    energy, and material products to enhance our
    lives? Are we stewards and caretakers of the
    earth, or do we have the right, perhaps the
    obligation, to exploit the earth for human
    well-being? In cases where the two are
    incompatible (as often happens in impoverished
    third world countries) which should take
    priority? These are real issues , but to frame
    the debate as a choice between killing animals or
    people is an unfair caricature.

28
Straw Person IV
  • Also, cant environmentalism be compatible with
    the welfare of human beings? The world can
    survive without people, but people cannot survive
    without the world.

29
Poisoning the well
  • A sister fallacy to straw person is poisoning the
    well. Here one side in an argument is placed in
    a position where it cannot refute the other
    without discrediting itself. This is done by
    making the position an undesirable one for any
    rational or decent person to hold.
  • For example, a moralist might argue, Women who
    support abortion are selfish and godless people.
    They put their own needs above everything and
    everyone else, and reject the divine gift of a
    childs life. Since most women would not want
    to be regarded as selfish and godless, they might
    abandon the argument for abortion on demand.

30
Poisoning the well II
  • Taking the opposite line, a feminist might argue,
    The right of a woman to have an abortion, to do
    with her body as she pleases , is opposed only by
    reactionary men who want to keep women in their
    traditional roles. Every right-thinking person
    knows this to be true. At this point any man
    who believes otherwise is reluctant to oppose
    abortion for fear of being regarded as a
    reactionary male and not a right-thinking person.
    Instances of poisoning the well happen all of
    the time in daily life. If a couple is
    quarreling the husband might say, I find you so
    defensive and your constant denials that you are
    defensive only prove my point. It is impossible
    then for the women to defend herself, since that
    would only confirm the defensiveness.

31
Poisoning the well III
  • We know we are in the presence of the fallacy
    whenever we come across statements such as Any
    caring or concerned person will agree that, or
    Those who reject my solution are part of the
    problem, Only an idiot would believe
  • In arguments, if we come across the ploy of
    poisoning the well we should expose it for what
    it is an attempt to place anyone who disagrees
    in an impossible position.

32
Slippery Slope
  • In the slippery slope fallacy we make the mistake
    of thinking that if we take one step along a
    certain path then nothing can stop us from
    sliding inevitably to our ruin. That is, once we
    set foot on the slippery slope we are bound to
    end up in disaster. The moral, or course, is
    that we had better avoid taking that first step.
  • Sometimes the fallacy of the slippery slope is
    described as the domino effect a slight push
    on one domino will topple the others and set a
    whole train of events in motion.

33
Slippery Slope II
  • At other times it is referred to as opening the
    floodgates so that we are inundated and
    overwhelmed by the forces that we have released.
    The English often refer to the thin edge of the
    wedge, which suggests that once we allow an
    opening this will be pushed to some greater,
    undesirable result. Still other metaphors are
    we mustnt let the genii our of the bottle,
    there is a ripple effect, give them an inch
    and theyll take a mile, events can begin to
    snowball (producing an avalanche), and if the
    camel gets his nose in the tent, hell soon have
    his entire body inside.

34
Slippery Slope III
  • Bureaucrats commit a common example of the
    slippery slope fallacy when they say, I would
    like to help you but if I make an exception for
    you I will have to make an exception for everyone
    else. Maybe in your situation there are
    extenuating circumstances but it is better to
    stick to the rules, otherwise everybody will
    claim they are a special case. The fallacy, of
    course, is to assume that once you initiate a
    course of action it is unstoppable. In fact,
    that is rarely true. That does not mean that
    rules are made to be broken but that it is
    possible to break rules without destroying them.

35
Slippery Slope IV
  • Very few rules are without legitimate exceptions,
    so if bureaucrats insist on absolute rules, they
    are bound to commit injustices. Of course, any
    one who claims an exception has the burden of
    proof to show why the exception should be made.
  • Sometimes slippery slopes do exist. Some
    developments in science and technology can be
    dangerous. When we split the atomic nucleus we
    used the energy for bombs. However, we cannot
    assume that whenever we take a first step we
    invariable lose control of events, that actions
    once unleashed must run their course and produce
    disaster. Usually we are faced with a flight of
    stairs, not a long slippery slope, and we can
    rest on any one of them.

36
Gamblers Fallacy
  • The gamblers fallacy is another important
    mistake to notice because it can trap people in a
    cycle of hope and desperation. Gambling has
    become an enormous business in the United States,
    exceeding the revenues of movies, books, and
    recorded music combined. In 1993 alone gambling
    revenues exceeded 30 billion. As a result of
    gaming, Las Vegas went from a small desert town
    of three thousand people to a city of one
    million, and states are now competing with Indian
    tribes in the race to build casinos.

37
Gamblers Fallacy II
  • The gamblers fallacy is one of the factors that
    keep people gambling, and it is usually described
    in terms of the maturity of the chances. A
    person playing roulette, for example, will wait
    to see which number has not come up in one
    hundred or two hundred spins of the wheel. Then
    she will bet on that number on the assumption
    that, according to statistical probability, the
    roulette ball is due to fall in that numbered
    compartment. However, at each turn of the wheel,
    each number has an equal chance of being chosen.

38
Gamblers Fallacy III
  • You flip a coin ten times, and each time it comes
    up heads. But on the 11th flip, will it come up
    heads again, or tails? If you ask a random group
    of people, you will likely get two different
    answers.
  • The first will be that the coin will surely come
    up heads again - it's already done so 10 times in
    a row, so the odds must be in favor of it
    happening again. The second answer will be that
    is must come up tails on the 11th flip, because
    it came up heads 10 times now and the coin is
    "due" to go the other way by now.

39
Gamblers Fallacy IV
  • But both answers are wrong, and both are the
    different sides of the gambler's fallacy. Even if
    we come up with 10,000 heads in a row, the odds
    of number 10,001 being tails is still only 50/50
    (assuming that the coin is "fair", of course).
    The law of averages does not change and a random
    system does not develop a "memory." The gambler's
    fallacy represents the very real human desire to
    find some sort meaning and pattern in what
    appears to be a random system.
  • As the French mathematician Joseph Bertrand
    remarked, the coin has neither memory or
    consciousness.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com